Is Euclid's Fourth Postulate Redundant?

  • Thread starter Thread starter lugita15
  • Start date Start date
AI Thread Summary
Euclid's fourth Postulate, stating that "all right angles are equal," is often perceived as straightforward but raises questions about its necessity. While some argue it may be redundant, David Hilbert's work suggests it could be derived from his axioms, challenging Euclid's classification of it as a postulate. The discussion highlights that Hilbert's proof relies on axioms that Euclid could accept, indicating a potential pathway for Euclid to have proven the fourth Postulate as a theorem. Participants emphasize the need for a clear step-by-step demonstration to establish its redundancy within Euclid's framework. Ultimately, the conversation revolves around the relationship between Euclid's and Hilbert's geometrical systems and the implications for foundational assumptions in geometry.
lugita15
Messages
1,553
Reaction score
15
Euclid's Elements start with five Postulates, including the fifth one, the famous Parallel Postulate. Less well known, however, is the Postulate that forms the basis for the fifth: the fourth one, which states that "all right angles are equal." Students who see this for the first time might find this puzzling, because obviously two angles which are equal to a 90 degree angle are equal to each other, since Common Notion 1 says that "things which are equal to the same thing are are also equal to one another". But then they realize that the matter is so straightforward: the definition of a right angle is an angle produced when two lines intersect each other and produce equal adjacent angles, and it's not clear why an angle produced by one such pair of lines should bear any relation to an angle produced by another such pair of lines.

So Euclid's fourth Postulate is not redundant for the reason that beginning students might think. But my question is, is it nevertheless a redundant postulate, although for far less trivial reasons? David Hilbert, in his Foundations of Geometry (Grundlagen der Geometrie in German), claims to prove Euclid's fourth Postulate in theorem 15 (on page 19 of the PDF or page 13 according to the book's internal page numbering), prefacing the proof by saying "it is possible to deduce the following simple theorem, which Euclid held - although it seems to me wrongly - to be an axiom."

Now it's fair to say that Hilbert was working in a different (and more rigorous) system of axioms than Euclid was, but I think Hilbert's proof should be seriously considered for two reasons. First of all, why would he dub Euclid's decision to call "all right angles are equal" a Postulate as "wrong" if it merely reflected a stylistic difference concerning what you choose as starting assumptions and what you consider theorems? But more importantly, by tracing back all the assumptions used in the proof of theorem 15, it seems to me that only four of Hilbert's axioms are ultimately used: IV 3, IV 4, IV 5, and IV 6. And I don't think Euclid would have objected to any of these statements:

1. IV 3 follows directly from Euclid's Common Notion 2.

2. IV 4 is partly stated in Euclid's Book I Proposition 23, which doesn't depend on the fourth postulate, and the part of IV 4 which (I think) is not stated is easily provable in Euclid's system.

3. IV 5 follows from Euclid's Common Notion 1.

4. IV 6 is just part of Euclid's Book I Proposition 4, which doesn't depend on the fourth postulate at all.

So could Euclid have proven his fourth Postulate as a theorem instead of just assuming it?

Any help would be greatly appreciated.

Thank You in Advance.
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
I think you need to show that the fourth postulate follows from the other four alone to consider that it is redundant to Euclid.
 
Simon Bridge said:
I think you need to show that the fourth postulate follows from the other four alone to consider that it is redundant to Euclid.
Well, I showed that all of Hilbert's assumptions in the proof were either assumed or proven by Euclid independent of the fourth postulate, so what more is needed?
 
I'm not so sure that you did - you certainly asserted that this was the case.
You should be able to work it backwards so that you can start from Euclid to get his fourth without assuming it.
It should be straight forward enough to show step-by-step, and provides a way to confirm what you've done.
Which is what you need - or did I misunderstand your question?
 
Insights auto threads is broken atm, so I'm manually creating these for new Insight articles. In Dirac’s Principles of Quantum Mechanics published in 1930 he introduced a “convenient notation” he referred to as a “delta function” which he treated as a continuum analog to the discrete Kronecker delta. The Kronecker delta is simply the indexed components of the identity operator in matrix algebra Source: https://www.physicsforums.com/insights/what-exactly-is-diracs-delta-function/ by...
Suppose ,instead of the usual x,y coordinate system with an I basis vector along the x -axis and a corresponding j basis vector along the y-axis we instead have a different pair of basis vectors ,call them e and f along their respective axes. I have seen that this is an important subject in maths My question is what physical applications does such a model apply to? I am asking here because I have devoted quite a lot of time in the past to understanding convectors and the dual...
Thread 'Imaginary Pythagoras'
I posted this in the Lame Math thread, but it's got me thinking. Is there any validity to this? Or is it really just a mathematical trick? Naively, I see that i2 + plus 12 does equal zero2. But does this have a meaning? I know one can treat the imaginary number line as just another axis like the reals, but does that mean this does represent a triangle in the complex plane with a hypotenuse of length zero? Ibix offered a rendering of the diagram using what I assume is matrix* notation...
Back
Top