Murray Gell-Mann on Entanglement

  • I
  • Thread starter Thecla
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Entanglement
  • Featured
In summary: I think it's a little more subtle than "non-local means measurement-dependent".In summary, most physicists working in this field agree that when you measure one of the photons it does something to the other one. It doesn't mean that they reject non-locality.
  • #71
Maybe, I don't understand the question right, because I don't see, where there should be a problem. I just measure the observable I want. If I want to measure one observable at a time ##t_1## and then another on the same system at ##t_2## I just do so. What should I update? Of course, when predicting what's measured at ##t_1## I have to somehow describe what happens to the system due to the interaction with the measurement device at the first measurement. I also don't know what you mean by "Bayesian update". If measurement number 1 is a von Neumann filter measurement, of course I update the state in the usual sense. Also, why shouldn't it be possible to do a second measuerement on the same system within the ensemble? It depends of course what you do to the system with the 1st measurement. If I absorb the photon in the 1st measurement, of course, I cannot measure anything on this very same photon at a later time.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #72
Shayan.J said:
That makes sense for QFT. But that means NRQM doesn't need collapse because Galilean transformations preserve simultaneity of the experiments.

But Galilean transformations are an approximation valid only when speeds are slow or separation distances between events are not very very large. It's hardly worth using it to form a worldview.
 
  • Like
Likes ddd123
  • #73
Simon Phoenix said:
OK - that's fair enough - but does assuming a naïve collapse model actually lead one to derive any inconsistent experimental results?

I would say that it doesn't. Instantaneous physical collapse is incompatible with the principles of Special Relativity, but I don't think it is incompatible with any experimental evidence.
 
  • #74
vanhees71 said:
Maybe, I don't understand the question right, because I don't see, where there should be a problem. I just measure the observable I want. If I want to measure one observable at a time ##t_1## and then another on the same system at ##t_2## I just do so. What should I update?

The wave function used at time [itex]t_2[/itex]. You prepare a system in state [itex]|\psi\rangle[/itex]. At time [itex]t_1[/itex], the state has evolved to some new state, [itex]|\psi(t_1)\rangle = e^{-iHt_1} |\psi \rangle[/itex]. At this moment, you perform a measurement of observable [itex]O[/itex] and get result [itex]\lambda[/itex]. Then for predictions about measurements at time [itex]t_2[/itex], you don't use [itex]|\psi(t_2)\rangle[/itex], you use [itex]|\psi'(t_2)\rangle[/itex], where [itex]|\psi'(t_2)\rangle = e^{-i H (t_2 - t_1)} \Pi_{O,\lambda} e^{-iH t_1} |\psi \rangle[/itex], where [itex]\Pi_{O,\lambda}[/itex] is the projection operator that projects onto the subspace of the Hilbert space corresponding to eigenvalue [itex]\lambda[/itex] of operator [itex]O[/itex]. So the "update" being discussed is switching from [itex]|\psi(t_1)\rangle = e^{-iHt_1} |\psi\rangle[/itex] to [itex]\Pi_{O,\lambda} |\psi(t_1)\rangle[/itex]. That update is what people mean by "collapse of the wave function".
 
  • #75
Sure, this describes a von Neumann Filter measurement. This update, however does not mean that there's an action at a distance with a far distant entangled part of the system I've measured.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #76
vanhees71 said:
But what is then "collapse" other than that A updates her knowledge due to the achieved polarization measurement of her photon (and the knowledge that it is polarization-entangled before her measurement)? Nothing happens to B's photon, and B still has unpolarized photons. So indeed Gell-Mann is right in his statement that nothing happens to B's photon!
How can we describe "nothing happens to B's photon" in a bit more experimentally accessible way? Would you agree to formulation that "if A has measured it's photon at different angle identical measurement of B's photon would (could) give the same result"?
 
  • #77
The reason I can see Gell-Mann's point is that I just don't understand why anyone would want to imagine that measuring one photon does something to the other. There can be reference frames that don't even agree which measurement happened first, nor should it matter-- you have a correlation, it's part of the system. We used to think all the information needed to predict a correlation was either "carried with" each piece of the system independently, or would involve some kind of propagating signal between the parts, but quantum mechanics gave us a well-tested formalism that says that doesn't work, instead correlations are holistic. So why not just accept that correlations are holistic? We've had so many other classical notions that we discarded, like absolute time and space or the idea that two identical preparations could not lead to different outcomes, so from whence comes the need to hang on to the old notion that all information works like attributes "carried with" pieces of a system, coupled with "influences" that propagate between the pieces? We find observationally that correlations are holistic, and a Bell state successfully encodes those holistic correlations, so why tack on some extraneous mechanism for moving those correlations around from place to place like an "influence"? The very idea that a two-photon system can be comprised of two separate photons is already a notion we should look at with suspicion (because of exchange symmetries), so why take it even farther to imagine those two dubious separate photons can do things to each other?
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn
  • #78
Ken G said:
The reason I can see Gell-Mann's point is that I just don't understand why anyone would want to imagine that measuring one photon does something to the other. There can be reference frames that don't even agree which measurement happened first, nor should it matter-- you have a correlation, it's part of the system. We used to think all the information needed to predict a correlation was either "carried with" each piece of the system independently, or would involve some kind of propagating signal between the parts, but quantum mechanics gave us a well-tested formalism that says that doesn't work, instead correlations are holistic. So why not just accept that correlations are holistic? We've had so many other classical notions that we discarded, like absolute time and space or the idea that two identical preparations could not lead to different outcomes, so from whence comes the need to hang on to the old notion that all information works like attributes "carried with" pieces of a system, coupled with "influences" that propagate between the pieces? We find observationally that correlations are holistic, and we have a mathematical formalism for encoding holistic correlations, so why not just accept that? The very idea that a two-photon system can be comprised of two separate photons is already a notion we should look at with suspicion, so why take it even farther to imagine those two dubious separate photons can do things to each other?

I think it is because with the other replacements for the old notions you could still form a picture of what happens inbetween preparation and measurement. Even giving up determinism let's you form a picture, because you just have a different rule for an instantaneous effect. Not having any picture and working in the blind is probably crossing a boundary for how much people are ready to give up. I mean what else could you give up after that if not predictability and thus science itself?
 
  • #79
vanhees71 said:
Sure, this describes a von Neumann Filter measurement. This update, however does not mean that there's an action at a distance with a far distant entangled part of the system I've measured.

Why doesn't it? The state of the distant component has changed as a result of your measurement.
 
  • #80
Ken G said:
The reason I can see Gell-Mann's point is that I just don't understand why anyone would want to imagine that measuring one photon does something to the other. There can be reference frames that don't even agree which measurement happened first, nor should it matter-- you have a correlation, it's part of the system. We used to think all the information needed to predict a correlation was either "carried with" each piece of the system independently, or would involve some kind of propagating signal between the parts, but quantum mechanics gave us a well-tested formalism that says that doesn't work, instead correlations are holistic.

It seems to me that "holistic" and "nonlocal" might mean the same thing, here.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim and ddd123
  • #81
stevendaryl said:
Why doesn't it? The state of the distant component has changed as a result of your measurement.

I understand that the "state" can be interpreted as subjective, rather than objective, but what is there to a particle, other than its state? There is nothing objective, is there? If you assume the existence of something objective (observer-independent) about a particle, and say that the quantum-mechanical state only reflects our information about this, then that's basically a hidden-variables theory, and Bell showed that such a theory has to be nonlocal. If you don't assume that there is anything objective about particles, then it seems like the question of FTL influences is moot. If the distant particle doesn't have any independent reality, then what could it mean to influence it nonlocally?
 
  • #82
stevendaryl said:
Why doesn't it? The state of the distant component has changed as a result of your measurement.
But that interpretation contradicts the locality of the interaction between A's photon and her polarization measurement apparatus. Also if Alice measures something else of her photon after it has passed the polarization filter, say directed to let through H-photons (which with utmost accuracy can indeed be made a v Neumann filter measurement!), all the outcomes of further measurements on her photon are described by associating the polarization state ##|H \rangle## with it. For A it's totally irrelevant what's the state of B's photon, as is for B whatever A does with her photon. The correlations due to the entanglement, which itself is due to the production of the entangled photon pair in the very beginning, can, however be observed by comparing the measurement protocols with accurate timestamps of each single-photon detection event by A and B. From this point of view (the minimal statistical interpretation) there is not need for assuming a collapse at all, and that prevents this interpretation from leading to inconsistency with the very foundations of relativistic QFT!
 
  • #83
vanhees71 said:
But that interpretation contradicts the locality of the interaction between A's photon and her polarization measurement apparatus.

If you posit, as Von Neumann did, the existence of two kinds of processes: (1) evolution according to Schrodinger's equation (or the equivalent for QFT), and (2) measurements, then nonlocality of the second type doesn't contradict locality for the first type. Of course, that's unsatisfying, because measurements (or observations) surely must be explainable in terms of the quantum mechanics of macroscopic devices, but it seems that any way of making sense of the Born probabilities involves making a distinction between macroscopic and microscopic phenomena. There are no probabilities involved in the evolution of a single electron. There are no probabilities involved in the evolution of two electrons. Probabilities only come into play in the interaction of something large enough to count as an observer, or a measuring device.
 
  • #84
vanhees71 said:
For A it's totally irrelevant what's the state of B's photon, as is for B whatever A does with her photon.
So you agree with this statement, right? - "If A has measured it's photon at different angle identical measurement of B's photon would (could) give the same result."
 
  • #85
I don't know how you can say "For A it's totally irrelevant what's the state of B's photon". If Alice knew the state of Bob's photon, then she would know the state of her own photon. So the state of Bob's photon is relevant to Alice.
 
  • #86
vanhees71 said:
I disagree, and that's also not in accordance with what Peres writes in the here discussed article. Again, you have to distinguish between longranged-correlations ("nonlocality" realized by entanglement also in relativistic QFT) and local interactions (realized by microcausality of the local observables and locality of the interaction Hamiltonian, as also clearly specified by Peres; he gives even a stronger argument, why relativistic QT should be realized as local relativistic QFT, then Weinberg in QT of Fields vol. I!).

Do you disagree with this statement: "Before Alice's measurement the state is ##|hh \rangle + |vv \rangle##, and after the measurement the state collapses to ##|hh \rangle## if Alice measures her photon to be horizontal"?

It's the same as what Peres starts his abstract with: " If several interventions performed on a quantum system are localized in mutually space-like regions, they will be recorded as a sequence of “quantum jumps” in one Lorentz frame, and as a different sequence of jumps in another Lorentz frame."

Peres also says in his first sentence of the text: "Quantum measurements [1] are usually considered as quasi-instantaneous processes. In particular, they affect the wave function instantaneously throughout the entire configuration space."

The quantum jumps are obviously nonlocal. If they were local, his whole article would be trivial. It is because they are nonlocal that one has to ask whether that nonlocality can be consistent with locality. The answer is yes, nonlocality can be consistent with locality.

Furthermore Peres writes: "Returning to the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen conundrum, we must analyze whether it actually involves a genuine quantum nonlocality. Such a claim has led some authors to suggest the possibility of superluminal communication."

Thus for Peres:
wave function collapse: fake quantum nonlocality
superluminal communication: genuine quantum nonlocality
no superluminal communication: genuine quantum locality

So fake quantum nonlocality is consistent with genuine quantum locality.
 
Last edited:
  • #87
I don't know, what you mean by measuring A's photon at different angle. The preparation in the entangled state ##|\Psi \rangle=|HV-VH \rangle## implies that, if A's photon is found to be polarized in an angle ##\phi## (relative to direction ##H##), then B's photon will be found in a state perpendicular to it.

Proof: Let ##|\phi \rangle=\cos phi |H \rangle + \sin \phi |V \rangle##. Then, if A finds her photon to be polarized in this direction, she adapts her state of the two-photon system to
$$|\Psi_A' \rangle=|\phi \rangle \langle \phi | \otimes 1 |\Psi \rangle=\cos^2 \phi |HV \rangle - \sin^2 \phi |VH \rangle + \cos \phi \sin \phi (|VV \rangle -|HH \rangle) = (\cos \phi |H \rangle + \sin \phi |V \rangle) \otimes (\cos \phi |V \rangle - \sin \phi |H \rangle) .$$
As it turns out, if you consider only those B photons for which A found polarization in direction ##|\phi \rangle##, then B will always find polarization in direction ##\phi+\pi/2##.

Note that the necessary filtering to figure this out needs the exchange of the measurement protocols between A and B. Both A and B measure just unpolarized photons, i.e., A's photon will go through the ##\phi##-polarization filter in 50% of the cases, and in these 50% of the cases B must measure his photon to be ##\phi+\pi/2## polarized. So there is a correlation between the photons but no action at a distance necessary to explain this result. The correlation is due to the preparation of the two-photon state in this entangled state and not due to A's polarization measurement on her single photon.
 
  • Like
Likes vortextor and bhobba
  • #88
atyy said:
Do you disagree with

Before Alice's measurement the state is ##|hh \rangle + |vv \rangle##, and after the measurement the state collapses to ##|hh \rangle## if Alice measures her photon to be horizontal?

It's kind of hard to know what to make of the situation. The situation is this:
  1. Initially, Bob's photon is unpolarized.
  2. After Alice's measurement, his photon is polarized in some direction, but Bob doesn't know which.
That's a change, of sorts, but it's not a change that makes any difference for Bob. The only "state" of Bob's photon that matters for his measurements is its density matrix. The initial density matrix describes a so-called "improper" mixed state, which is obtained from the two-photon pure state by tracing over Alice's photon. The final density matrix is a proper mixed state, which is obtained by taking a weighted sum of pure-states. So Bob's photon's state went from an improper mixed state to a proper mixed state, which seems like a change, but they are both described by the identical matrix. So from that point of view, nothing has changed for Bob.
 
  • #89
vanhees71 said:
I don't know, what you mean by measuring A's photon at different angle.

Just a general request about discussions here: If your comment is a direct response to a specific other comment, I would prefer that you either quote some part of the previous comment, or at least the name of the previous commenter.
 
  • #90
atyy said:
Do you disagree with this statement: "Before Alice's measurement the state is ##|hh \rangle + |vv \rangle##, and after the measurement the state collapses to ##|hh \rangle## if Alice measures her photon to be horizontal"?
Yes, I disagree with this statement. Correct is: If A's photon passes the h-polarization filter she associates the state ##hh \rangle## to the two photons. However, her measurement has no instantaneous influence on B's photon, i.e., there must not be a collapse if the interpretation should be consistent with the very construction of QED as a local relativistic QFT, and you don't need it!

It's the same as what Peres starts his abstract with: " If several interventions performed on a quantum system are localized in mutually space-like regions, they will be recorded as a sequence of “quantum jumps” in one Lorentz frame, and as a different sequence of jumps in another Lorentz frame."
Well, I'm also against the use of the word quantum jumps, but I guess Peres has the right thing in mind when he states this, and he is right that the temporal sequence for space-like separated "interventions" is frame dependent, which implies that one intervention cannot have a causal influence on the other space-like separated intervention. That's the whole point of our disagreement. In my (and if I understand him right also Peres's) notion of the state as epistemic (particularly the "update" or if you wish to call it with another unsharp word "quantum jump" of the state after a "filtering intervention" as in our example here) there is no tension between causality and relativistic QFT whatsoever, and that's so by construction of the QFT, and Peres's argument in the paper is just another very convincing argument for why (at least) the Hamilton density operator has to commute at spacelike separation of the arguments, i.e., if ##(x-y) \cdot (x-y)<0## (west-coast convention of the metric) you must have ##[\hat{\mathcal{H}}(x),\hat{\mathcal{H}}(y)]=0##. Usually one assumes even more, i.e., that any two local operators commute at spacelike separation of their arguments.
 
  • #91
vanhees71 said:
Yes, I disagree with this statement. Correct is: If A's photon passes the h-polarization filter she associates the state ##hh \rangle## to the two photons. However, her measurement has no instantaneous influence on B's photon, i.e., there must not be a collapse if the interpretation should be consistent with the very construction of QED as a local relativistic QFT, and you don't need it!Well, I'm also against the use of the word quantum jumps, but I guess Peres has the right thing in mind when he states this, and he is right that the temporal sequence for space-like separated "interventions" is frame dependent, which implies that one intervention cannot have a causal influence on the other space-like separated intervention. That's the whole point of our disagreement. In my (and if I understand him right also Peres's) notion of the state as epistemic (particularly the "update" or if you wish to call it with another unsharp word "quantum jump" of the state after a "filtering intervention" as in our example here) there is no tension between causality and relativistic QFT whatsoever, and that's so by construction of the QFT, and Peres's argument in the paper is just another very convincing argument for why (at least) the Hamilton density operator has to commute at spacelike separation of the arguments, i.e., if ##(x-y) \cdot (x-y)<0## (west-coast convention of the metric) you must have ##[\hat{\mathcal{H}}(x),\hat{\mathcal{H}}(y)]=0##. Usually one assumes even more, i.e., that any two local operators commute at spacelike separation of their arguments.

Well, whatever it is you need the mathematics, and it is true that the state is assigned to spacelike surface, and the "update" takes place instantaneously on that surface.
 
  • #92
vanhees71 said:
I don't know, what you mean by measuring A's photon at different angle.
Let's say A measured her photon with polarizer at an angle ##\alpha_1##. B measured his photon at an angle ##\beta_1## and got result "+".
Now what it means to say that "it's totally irrelevant for B what A does with her photon"?
I propose such meaning: if A would have measured her photon with polarizer at an angle ##\alpha_2## then B measuring his photon at the same angle ##\beta_1## could still get result "+".

Or do you have on mind different meaning for "it's totally irrelevant for B what A does with her photon"?
 
  • #93
vanhees71 said:
But that interpretation contradicts the locality of the interaction between A's photon and her polarization measurement apparatus.
But according to the minimal ensemble interpretation (MEI), quantum theory says nothing about the interaction between an individual photon and an individual apparatus. It only talks about a large ensemble of interacting photon-apparatus pairs. At the level of ensemble the interactions are local, but there is no guarantee that interactions are local even at the individual level. It could be that individual interactions contain a non-local part, but that these non-local parts cancel-up in the average at the ensemble level. This is a logical possibility that does not contradict known facts about quantum theory (including relativistic QFT) in the MEI form.
 
  • #94
stevendaryl said:
It seems to me that "holistic" and "nonlocal" might mean the same thing, here.
I think there's an important difference. "Nonlocal" still implies an influence of sorts, merely one that is not constrained by the speed of light. "Holistic" takes the mathematics at face value-- the system is a single entity, not made of parts that "influence" each other. If there are not parts, there is not any issue with propagation of influences, either slower or faster than c. One simply rejects the concept of a part influencing another part, and poof, nothing "nonlocal" there, it's just a single thing. That's what the mathematics is, after all-- a single thing, with all the correlations built in.

By the way, the simplest way to think of the state as a "single thing" is to treat it as information, rather than a physical entity. One can imagine there is a physical entity out there if one likes, but that's not what the scientist deals in, the scientist deals in information and using information to make and test predictions. We all create a sense of something "physical" during that process, of course, but we needn't mistake our intuitive imaginings for any part of what we are actually doing when we carry out a test. Above all, we don't tell the mathematical entities we manipulate that they must be subservient to our intuitive pictures-- we must train our intuition to the mathematics that works, not the other way around.
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn
  • #95
Ken G said:
I think there's an important difference. "Nonlocal" still implies an influence of sorts, merely one that is not constrained by the speed of light.

I think that nonlocal doesn't necessarily imply FTL influences. Local to me means that the most complete description of the universe "factors" into descriptions of small regions of spacetime, and that the evolution of one region depends only on what's true in neighboring regions. Quantum mechanics is not local in this sense, because in the case of distant entangled systems, the most complete description of the universe does not factor into a bunch of local descriptions. For example, in EPR for photons, the most complete description for Alice's photon is that for any orientation of a polarizing filter, the photon has a 50% chance of passing through that filter. The most complete description for Bob's photon is the same. But the most complete description for Alice, together with the most complete description for Bob doesn't add up to the most complete description for the Alice/Bob system, since it doesn't include the perfect correlation between their results when their filters are aligned.

Classical probabilities can be nonlocal in this sense, as well, but in that case, there is a more complete description that is local.
 
  • #96
Let me add to my previous point about the difference between "nonlocal" and "holistic." A lot is made of entanglement as being "spooky", but for some reason I never hear the term "spooky" in the context of the Pauli exclusion principle. Why not? Is not the PEP just as "nonlocal" as EPR? For example, we have stellar remnants the size of planet Earth called "white dwarfs" which can cool to the point that they are completely degenerate, in principle. By then, the star is still the size of Earth, it contains some 1057 electrons, and each of those electrons has some ghastly kinetic energy equivalent to a billion Kelvin if they weren't degenerate. Yet with all those electrons zinging around with all that kinetic energy, not a single collision is allowed to occur, and not a single photon is allowed to be emitted (in the idealized limit). Talk about entanglement! The identical nature of those Fermions is such that if you think that is a "system of parts" that are "nonlocally influencing" each other, each electron must be influenced by all the others so that it can "know" it is not allowed to enter a previously occupied state-- across an object the size of Earth. Why isn't that "spooky action at a distance"? If one wants EPR to be a "nonlocal influence," then a black dwarf is the mother of all nonlocal influences. To me, it just makes more sense to think a black dwarf is all one thing, and the information we have about that thing tells us it cannot emit light-- without any "parts" talking to any other "parts." It just isn't made of parts any more, our naive notion that matter is "made of particles" breaks down when the particles are identical and degenerate. One can imagine that a proton is "made of quarks and virtual gluons", but what sense does it make to say something is made of virtual things? We should just accept that our concept of what it means to be "comprised of" tiny pieces is simply not a general description of reality that should work in all situations.
 
  • #97
Ken G said:
Let me add to my previous point about the difference between "nonlocal" and "holistic." A lot is made of entanglement as being "spooky", but for some reason I never hear the term "spooky" in the context of the Pauli exclusion principle. Why not? Is not the PEP just as "nonlocal" as EPR?

I think that they're very closely related. The nonlocality of EPR is due to having nonfactorable composite wave functions, and the Pauli exclusion principle is a constraint on such wave functions.
 
  • #98
stevendaryl said:
I think that nonlocal doesn't necessarily imply FTL influences. Local to me means that the most complete description of the universe "factors" into descriptions of small regions of spacetime, and that the evolution of one region depends only on what's true in neighboring regions. Quantum mechanics is not local in this sense, because in the case of distant entangled systems, the most complete description of the universe does not factor into a bunch of local descriptions.
I agree that you are using "nonlocal" in the way I mean "holistic," and that's probably because you are not buying off on the idea that nonlocality must be enforced by "influences" that happen "instantaneously" in an EPR setup. But for those who do wish to maintain a sense of fractured locality, a "pieceness" or "discreteness" to systems that are cobbled together from smaller entities plus influences between those entities, they need a concept of "nonlocal" that does not violate their "discreteness" concept. It's for them that a distinction between nonlocal and holistic must be made.

In other words, to me "holistic" differs from "nonlocal" in the sense that when the ancient Greeks wondered if matter was continuous or comprised of discrete "atoms", they left out a third possibility: it could be analyzed in terms of discrete bits in some situations, continuous fluids in others, and still in others, it could not be thought of either as discrete local bits-and-influences, nor as a continuum maintained by either propagating or nonlocal influences, but instead, a system could be all one thing. I don't think they even imagined that possibility, so how amazing is it that we have come to it with the mathematics of quantum mechanics-- we should embrace that fascinating new possibility, rather than fight it because it is outside our expectations.
For example, in EPR for photons, the most complete description for Alice's photon is that for any orientation of a polarizing filter, the photon has a 50% chance of passing through that filter. The most complete description for Bob's photon is the same. But the most complete description for Alice, together with the most complete description for Bob doesn't add up to the most complete description for the Alice/Bob system, since it doesn't include the perfect correlation between their results when their filters are aligned.
Yes exactly, but notice the significance of how you've built up this scenario-- the "merging" that happened to create the holistic system was a merging of Alice's and Bob's information, more so than a merging of their photons. They don't even possesses their own photons, any more than a white dwarf possesses separate distinguishable electrons. What is holistic is the information, when we treat it together, or about individual photons, when we treat it that way. The system is happening at the level of how we are treating the information, not the sum of two individual electrons and their experimental outcomes. A photon doesn't own its own experimental outcome, a scientist owns that.
 
  • Like
Likes Jilang
  • #99
secur said:
But Gell-Mann said: "People say loosely ,crudely, wrongly that when you measure one of the photons it does something to the other one. It doesn't."
He's not agnostic. He's strongly denying any causative link.
I'm not sure that's a fair assessment of Gell-Mann's claim, because it's not clear exactly what's being denied when we're dealing with a denial of something that has been stated "loosely, crudely". Or as Bhobba said:
bhobba said:
Yes - but its for a lay audience. I think a bit of latitude is reasonable.
 
  • #101
stevendaryl said:
I think that they're very closely related. The nonlocality of EPR is due to having nonfactorable composite wave functions, and the Pauli exclusion principle is a constraint on such wave functions.
Right, exactly, they are indeed very closely related. So we need an approach to both that resolves the same issues. But no one talks about spooky action at a distance when they say the ground state of an atom has higher energy levels, or when they talk about white dwarfs. No one says that an excited electron in an atom can only drop down to unoccupied states because "nonlocal influences" from the other electrons collapse its state. I think that's because it sounds local to say you cannot sit in a chair if someone else is already there, but that's not why the PEP works, it works because the exchange antisymmetry is holistic. The actual reason an electron cannot go into an occupied state is not because another electron is already there, that very language suggests electrons have their own identities-- it can't do it expressly because it does not have its own identity, the system is holistic.
 
  • #102
Holism sounds pretty much like nonlocality to me, since a system like that is extended in space.
 
  • #103
ddd123 said:
Holism sounds pretty much like nonlocality to me, since a system like that is extended in space.
Is an iron atom in its ground state extended in space? The holistic elements are outside of spatial considerations, in general.
 
  • #104
Well it is extended in space. I don't understand the second sentence.
 
  • #105
My point is that the PEP has nothing to do with spatial extent, it works for the completely overlapping wavefunctions of the two electrons in the ground state of Helium, and it works for a white dwarf the size of Earth. It is about a system not being "made of parts", which is what I mean by holism. Not being made of parts is a much more fundamentally different way to think about a system than simply spatially extended and subject to superluminal influences as a result. I'm saying it makes more sense to say that EPR type effects come from the holism of the Bell state, and don't care at all about spatial extent.
 

Similar threads

Replies
5
Views
1K
  • Art, Music, History, and Linguistics
Replies
11
Views
597
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
7
Views
1K
Replies
22
Views
2K
Replies
19
Views
2K
Replies
40
Views
3K
Replies
33
Views
2K
  • General Discussion
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
3
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
31
Views
1K
Back
Top