I Murray Gell-Mann on Entanglement

  • I
  • Thread starter Thread starter Thecla
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Entanglement
  • #151
Demystifier said:
Fair enough! But do you agree with me that the dispute between you and atyy is not about physics, and not about interpretation, but only about language?
It would be only a discussion about language, if atyy hadn't claimed in the very beginning of this thread that Gell-Mann's view is wrong. I think it's very clear from the mathematics of QED that there is no instantaneous influence on B's photon by A's measurement of hers.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #152
vanhees71 said:
I think it's very clear from the mathematics of QED that there is no instantaneous influence on B's photon by A's measurement of hers.
Ah, this is a much more serious and subtle issue. I don't think that this is clear from mathematics of QED. See my post #93 on this thread!
 
  • #153
ddd123 said:
Anyway there is a line of research that shows a different link between entanglement and spatial issues: http://www.nature.com/news/the-quantum-source-of-space-time-1.18797 .
Wow, that's really a nice article, thank you. The way I interpret what it is saying is that it takes the AdS/CFT duality (which says that gravity in a 3D "bulk" under some conditions will act like a conformal field theory (without any gravity) on the 2D boundary of the bulk) and extends it to saying that the connectivity of space in the bulk is dual to the entanglement in the CFT on the boundary. If we think of connectivity of space as important for concepts like nonlocality, and if we interpret entanglement as fundamentally an issue about the holism of systems, then the article seems to be suggesting that our discussion about nonlocality vs. holism has an interesting duality as well: nonlocality in the bulk is dual to holism on the boundary. Put differently, the idea in the article is that the space in the bulk is in some sense "due to" entanglement on the boundary, such that space is "made of entanglement", as they like to say. That certainly puts our discussion into an interesting new light-- it would say that nonlocality and holism, though not the same thing any more than gravity and quantum mechanics are the same thing, do share a deep connection in that we get one when we look in the bulk, and we get the other when we look in the boundary.

The way I interpret all this is that the concept of the "parts" of a system is not a fundamental truth of how systems work, rather it is an idealization that works well when the entanglement in the holistic system is decohered enough to get away with treating the system as if it were made of parts. Similarly, the concept of "locality", i.e., that the parts can only enforce correlations in measurements by propagating subluminal signals, is also not a fundamental truth, it is an idealization that works well when, again, the entanglement on the boundary is sufficiently decohered. What all this means is, the limitation of not going faster than c, and the distinctions between spacelike and timelike separations, are not fundamental laws, they are just what happens in the bulk when entanglements on the boundary get decohered.

The key point of all this, in this interpretation, is that we could frame Gell-Mann's objection in the following terms. The reason it is "wrong" to say that entanglement is enforced by influences between the parts of the system is that it reverses the way we should be thinking about it. We should be saying that the idealization that systems are made of parts, and the idealization that those parts have different locations in spacetime, both work when entanglement breaks down. As such, entanglement does not need to be explained, it is the default state of things-- it is the concepts of parts and propagating influences that need to be explained, and those concepts only emerge when entanglement is broken. Perhaps you can think of "parts" and "influences" as the kind of behaviors that emerge when the symmetry associated with entanglement is broken, a symmetry about the unity (or holism) of systems. It really turns entanglement, and holism, on its ear to say that it is their absence that requires understanding, not their presence. So we don't need to explain why all electrons are indistinguishable, that's a symmetry-- we need to explain why we get away with imagining that they are different, and that they occupy different locations in space. It seems that somehow, all the motion we perceive through space might be traced back to changing coherences in the entanglements on the boundary. It's then not the nonlocality of entanglement that we need to understand, it is the origin of locality as that entanglement evolves that we need to understand.
 
  • Like
Likes ddd123
  • #154
Demystifier said:
Ah, this is a much more serious and subtle issue. I don't think that this is clear from mathematics of QED. See my post #93 on this thread!
Sure, what you say in #93 is part of the formalism. The states have probabilistic meaning and only probabilistic meaning (i.e. a statistical meaning for ensembles, i.e., repeated experiments with equally prepared systems). Of you somehow make states "more ontic" in some sense you are in serious trouble concerning causality!
 
  • #155
vanhees71 said:
It would be only a discussion about language, if atyy hadn't claimed in the very beginning of this thread that Gell-Mann's view is wrong. I think it's very clear from the mathematics of QED that there is no instantaneous influence on B's photon by A's measurement of hers.

If there were a definitive notion of the state of Bob's photon, then you could definitively prove that Alice has no effect on Bob's photon. But quantum mechanics doesn't actually give a definitive notion of the state of a single particle; it only has a notion of the state of the entire system.
 
  • Like
Likes zonde
  • #156
vanhees71 said:
Of you somehow make states "more ontic" in some sense you are in serious trouble concerning causality!
Well, you cannot get something for nothing. If gaining ontology means loosing relativistic causality, I can live with that (provided that I don't contradict any existing experiment). It is certainly possible that standard quantum theory in the MEI form is not the final theory. It is also possible that a better theory has more ontology and less relativistic causality than standard quantum theory.

Or perhaps your main problem is to understand why would one even want more ontology? Well, if MEI is perfect for you, then you can't understand it. Only if you can see an interesting question not answered by MEI, you can start to appreciate other (more ontological) interpretations of quantum theory.
 
Last edited:
  • #157
The state of Bob's photon is given by the reduced state
$$\hat{\rho}_{B}=\mathrm{Tr}_A \hat{\rho}_{AB}$$
with
$$\hat{\rho}_{AB} = \frac{1}{2} (|HV \rangle-|VH \rangle)(\langle HV|-\langle VH |).$$
The partial trace is
$$\hat{\rho}_B=\sum_{i,j,k=HV} |j \rangle \langle ij|\hat{\rho}_{AB}|ik \rangle \langle k|=\frac{1}{2} \hat{1}.$$
It's all very well defined in the formalism, and clearly Bob has unpolarized photons.
 
  • #158
vanhees71 said:
Sure, what you say in #93 is part of the formalism. The states have probabilistic meaning and only probabilistic meaning (i.e. a statistical meaning for ensembles, i.e., repeated experiments with equally prepared systems). Of you somehow make states "more ontic" in some sense you are in serious trouble concerning causality!

To me, the claim that states only have probabilistic meaning is not completely coherent. You prepare a system in some state. You use some device to measure a property of that system--for simplicity, a boolean-valued property--and the result is either that the dial points to "yes", with probability P_{yes}, or it points to "no", with probability P_{no}. Say the dial points to "yes". Would you then say that it is in a particular state (namely, one with the dial pointing to "yes")? For macroscopic objects, is definitely not the case that states only have probabilistic meaning. But since a macroscopic object is (presumably) just a complicated arrangement of elementary particles, that would seem to mean that combinations of particles can have states that have more than just probabilistic meaning.
 
  • #159
This alone doesn't determine the state completely. See Ballentine, Quantum Mechanics for a detailed discussion on "state determination".
 
  • Like
Likes morrobay
  • #160
vanhees71 said:
The state of Bob's photon is given by the reduced state
$$\hat{\rho}_{B}=\mathrm{Tr}_A \hat{\rho}_{AB}$$
with
$$\hat{\rho}_{AB} = \frac{1}{2} (|HV \rangle-|VH \rangle)(\langle HV|-\langle VH |).$$
The partial trace is
$$\hat{\rho}_B=\sum_{ij=HV} |j \rangle \langle ij|\hat{\rho}_{AB}|ij \rangle \langle j|=\frac{1}{2} \hat{1}.$$
It's all very well defined in the formalism, and clearly Bob has unpolarized photons.

As I said to Simon, it's complicated to figure out what is subjective and what is objective in QM. Bob can describe his photon using such a density matrix. Later on, but before Bob has measured his photon, he may find out the result of Alice's measurement, and so he would update his density matrix to that of a pure state, |H\rangle\langle H|, maybe. It seems that Bob can understand this in two ways:
  1. It was always in that pure state, but he didn't know it, and his density matrix reflected his ignorance.
  2. It was once in an unpolarized state, but later changed its state to a polarized state.
It seems to me that both possibilities lead to difficulties, and it seems that one or the other must be true. Option 1 is a hidden-variables theory, ruled out by Bell, while option 2 requires a nonlocal interaction between Alice and Bob.
 
  • #161
vanhees71 said:
This alone doesn't determine the state completely. See Ballentine, Quantum Mechanics for a detailed discussion on "state determination".

Just a gentle reminder: It would be helpful to include in your posts what statement you are responding to.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #162
stevendaryl said:
As I said to Simon, it's complicated to figure out what is subjective and what is objective in QM. Bob can describe his photon using such a density matrix. Later on, but before Bob has measured his photon, he may find out the result of Alice's measurement, and so he would update his density matrix to that of a pure state, |H\rangle\langle H|, maybe. It seems that Bob can understand this in two ways:
  1. It was always in that pure state, but he didn't know it, and his density matrix reflected his ignorance.
  2. It was once in an unpolarized state, but later changed its state to a polarized state.
It seems to me that both possibilities lead to difficulties, and it seems that one or the other must be true. Option 1 is a hidden-variables theory, ruled out by Bell, while option 2 requires a nonlocal interaction between Alice and Bob.

Bob cannot but he must describe his photon by this statistical operator given that the pair is prepared in the state given above. Further, if Bob can find out A's result, then there is no problem with causality, because then his measurement is time-like separated and in the future lightcone of A's measurement event. Of course, B's photon is for B not in the pure state but in the state of an unpolarized photon before the measurement and before he as either gotten the information about A's outcome or has made his own measurement. Contrary to what you say the assignment of states is objective, it's defined by equivalence classes of preparation procedures.

Finally, 2. is the correct answer, but it doesn't need nonlocal interactions between A and B. B can only take notice of A's measurement result via a maximally luminally propagating signal and thus in this case his measurement is in the future light cone of A's measurement event, i.e., then his update of his knowledge to the pure state is objective and precisely not obtained in an instantaneous or nonlocal interaction.
 
  • #163
vanhees71 said:
The states have probabilistic meaning and only probabilistic meaning
Are you familiar with the PBR theorem?
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/PBR_theorem
This theorem seems to prove that state contains something more than mere probability.
 
  • #164
vanhees71 said:
Bob cannot but he must describe his photon by this statistical operator given that the pair is prepared in the state given above. Further, if Bob can find out A's result, then there is no problem with causality, because then his measurement is time-like separated and in the future lightcone of A's measurement event. Of course, B's photon is for B not in the pure state but in the state of an unpolarized photon before the measurement and before he as either gotten the information about A's outcome or has made his own measurement. Contrary to what you say the assignment of states is objective, it's defined by equivalence classes of preparation procedures.

Once again, could you please quote the relevant statement(s) that you are responding to?

As I said, your point of view seems slightly incoherent to me. You seem to be wanting to say both that
  • Bob's photon is objectively in an unpolarized state, initially.
  • After receiving information from Alice, he updates its state to a pure state (horizontally polarized, for example).
If the state is updated based on new information, that makes it subjective. That's sort of the definition of subjective probability, that it reflects the (lack of) information of the observer.
 
  • #165
Demystifier said:
Are you familiar with the PBR theorem? This theorem seems to prove that state contains something more than mere probability.
No. I've found the Nature Physics paper via google. What's the relation to my statement above? It seem that this is at least one of the final possibilities left by the paper, which I have to study first, to make up my mind about it of course. The final words in the paper read:

For these reasons and others, many will continue to view the
quantum state as representing information. One approach is to
take this to be information about possible measurement outcomes,
and not about the objective state of a system 23 . Another is to
construct concrete models of reality wherein one or more of
our assumptions fail.
 
  • #166
stevendaryl said:
Once again, could you please quote the relevant statement(s) that you are responding to?

As I said, your point of view seems slightly incoherent to me. You seem to be wanting to say both that
  • Bob's photon is objectively in an unpolarized state, initially.
  • After receiving information from Alice, he updates its state to a pure state (horizontally polarized, for example).
If the state is updated based on new information, that makes it subjective. That's sort of the definition of subjective probability, that it reflects the (lack of) information of the observer.
I don't know, how else I can refer to what I'm answering to than quoting the posting, which I did by hitting the reply button.

There is no contradiction. 1. Bob's photon is objectively in an unpolarized state because the state of the two-photon system is objective due to the preparation procedure (e.g., via parametric down conversion). 2. is also clear, because when you get new knowledge you update your probabilities according to this knowledge. Where is the contradiction?
 
  • #167
Demystifier said:
This theorem seems to prove that state contains something more than mere probability.

As I said to Vanhees71, I think that the idea that states only have a probabilistic meaning is incoherent. To make sense of quantum probabilities, you have to compile statistics of measurement results. But a measurement result is just a state of an observer, a persistent record, or a measurement device. So macroscopic objects must have a notion of "state" that is nonprobabilistic. Presumably, since macroscopic objects are made of microscopic objects, this means that a nonprobabilistic notion of state must somehow emerge from the microscopic notion of state.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim and Demystifier
  • #168
vanhees71 said:
There is no contradiction. 1. Bob's photon is objectively in an unpolarized state because the state of the two-photon system is objective due to the preparation procedure (e.g., via parametric down conversion). 2. is also clear, because when you get new knowledge you update your probabilities according to this knowledge. Where is the contradiction?

The contradiction is that the first notion of "state" is objective, while the second notion is subjective.
 
  • #169
stevendaryl said:
The contradiction is that the first notion of "state" is objective, while the second notion is subjective.
All notions of state as I use them are objective. It's given by a preparation procedure. In this case before A's measurement and B's noticing of her result, the state is given due to to the parametric down conversion, and after B's noticing of A's result it's due to that measurement. Here you through away half the ensemble, and this half of the ensemble is described by the corresponding pure state of B's photon.
 
  • #170
vanhees71 said:
It seem that this is at least one of the final possibilities left by the paper
According to the theorem, it is still possible that state is nothing more than a mere probability, provided that even non-entangled spatially separated systems can be statistically dependent. Are you sure that this possibility is more acceptable to you?

Anyway, the PBR theorem is certainly a very serious threat to the minimal ensemble interpretation of QM. So I would highly recommend you to study it and make your own opinion on it.
 
  • #171
vanhees71 said:
All notions of state as I use them are objective.

Maybe I misunderstood. Bob initially describes his photon as unpolarized. Later, Alice tells him the result of her measurement. Bob afterwards uses the pure state |H\rangle \langle H| to describe his photon's state. The change is a result of Bob acquiring new information, which makes it a subjective change, rather than an objective change. That's the definition of subjective probability--probability that is dependent on the information available to the observer.

"Subjective" doesn't mean "a matter of opinion". It means (in this case) a matter of information.
 
  • #172
stevendaryl said:
Maybe I misunderstood. Bob initially describes his photon as unpolarized. Later, Alice tells him the result of her measurement. Bob afterwards uses the pure state |H\rangle \langle H| to describe his photon's state. The change is a result of Bob acquiring new information, which makes it a subjective change, rather than an objective change. That's the definition of subjective probability--probability that is dependent on the information available to the observer.

"Subjective" doesn't mean "a matter of opinion".
I don't know what you mean by subjective vs. objective here. If a photon is measured to be H-polarized it's polarization state is ##|H \rangle \langle H|##, and if A measures V and B gets this information, given that before the two photons were in the polarization singlet state, B objectively knows that his photon is H-polarized, and thus that then his photon's state is described by ##|H \rangle \langle H|##.
 
  • #173
vanhees71 said:
I don't know what you mean by subjective vs. objective here.
Objective is when B gets "click" in H channel of his PBS at particular time window, subjective is when B expects to get "click" in H channel at particular time window.
 
  • #174
I don't think my basic question has been answered (or maybe I didn't understand the answer, which is quite likely :sorry:)

In the entanglement-swapping scheme we have prepared a state such that (1,2) are maximally entangled and (2,3) are maximally entangled. Given this then we can say for definite that there is initially no entanglement between particles 1 and 4. Now some measurement is performed on particles 2 and 3 (a Bell measurement) and after this measurement particles 1 and 4 are entangled.

If entanglement is a definite objective property then something physical has changed before and after measurement. The measurement part is critical since local unitary transformations on particles (2,3) cannot change the degree of correlation, or entropy of entanglement, between particles 1 and 4 - it requires a non-unitary process.

Another example would be to take a GHZ state of the form |111> + |000> as our initial state (described in the spin-z basis), and give one of the particles to each of Alice, Bob and Clive. Now one party, say Clive, makes a spin-x measurement and the other two particles of Alice and Bob (initially in a correlated but un-entangled state) are now in a maximally entangled state.

So assuming entanglement is a physical property we've (instantaneously?) effected some significant change to the state and the physical properties of 2 particles (non-entangled to entangled) that could be separated by some distance. Furthermore, this change cannot be described by purely unitary processes local to (2,3) - since the degree of entanglement between 1 and 4 is constant under such unitary processes. And similar considerations apply for the GHZ example too.

Maybe it's only me that has a problem with this - but then I don't view QM as applying only to ensembles - I think it works just fine for individual systems too.
 
  • #175
vanhees71 said:
I don't know what you mean by subjective vs. objective here.

I defined it many times: If the state is updated based on new information available to Bob, then it's subjective. If the state changed from \frac{1}{2} |H\rangle \langle H| + \frac{1}{2} |V\rangle \langle V| to |H\rangle \langle H| through no interaction with the photon, but only by Alice whispering something in Bob's ear, then that means that either:
  1. The state is subjective; it reflects Bob's information, or
  2. Bob was wrong about the initial state. (This would be the case if Bob initially thought that Alice's pet was a cat, and then Alice informed him that it was a dog. Dog versus cat is an objective difference, and if Bob initially thought it was a cat, then he was mistaken.)
The objective state of an object can only change by something being done to that object. The subjective state can be changed by the observer acquiring new information.
 
Last edited:
  • #176
Simon Phoenix said:
If entanglement is a definite objective property then something physical has changed before and after measurement. The measurement part is critical since local unitary transformations on particles (2,3) cannot change the degree of correlation, or entropy of entanglement, between particles 1 and 4 - it requires a non-unitary process.

I agree with you, but it seems to me that bringing up entanglement swapping just complicates things without adding any new feature. (Does it?)

Entanglement is a feature of the quantum state of a composite system. So asking whether entanglement is objective is a special case of asking whether the state is objective. The usual EPR experiment already raises that question. Initially, Bob's photon is described (by both Alice and Bob) as unpolarized, having the density matrix \frac{1}{2} |H\rangle \langle H| + \frac{1}{2} |V\rangle \langle V|. After Alice measures her photon, but before Bob finds out her result, Alice would describe Bob's photon as in the state |H\rangle \langle H|, while Bob would continue to use the unpolarized state.

Bob and Alice are then using different density matrices to describe the same photon. So either the state is subjective, or one of them is wrong. If the state is objective, and Alice is right about what that state is, then it means that Alice's measurement had an instantaneous effect on Bob's state.
 
  • #177
Demystifier said:
But you use the update, which is what atyy really means by "collapse".

So you and atyy agree on physics and on interpretation. You only disagree on the language. Atyy refuses to call it "update", and you refuse to translate his "collapse" as "update".

If fights over correct interpretation are not much relevant to physics, fights over correct language are even less relevant to physics. :H

It is more than semantics. vanhees71 says that collapse is not consistent with locality, whereas I say that collapse is consistent with locality.
 
  • #178
Demystifier said:
According to the theorem, it is still possible that state is nothing more than a mere probability, provided that even non-entangled spatially separated systems can be statistically dependent. Are you sure that this possibility is more acceptable to you?

Anyway, the PBR theorem is certainly a very serious threat to the minimal ensemble interpretation of QM. So I would highly recommend you to study it and make your own opinion on it.
I'll have a look at it. I take the publication in Nature as the final word on it, or is it rather v3 of the arXiv preprint the final word?

https://arxiv.org/abs/1111.3328
 
  • #179
atyy said:
It is more than semantics. vanhees71 says that collapse is not consistent with locality, whereas I say that collapse is consistent with locality.
The "collapse" as mere update is consistent with locality. But you open the possibility that collapse can be something more than that, in which case it is not consistent with locality. I think you confuse the readers by not always being explicit about which "collapse" do you have in mind.
 
  • #180
Demystifier said:
Anyway, the PBR theorem is certainly a very serious threat to the minimal ensemble interpretation of QM. So I would highly recommend you to study it and make your own opinion on it.

Well, the conclusion of PBR is not that mysterious to me. What it really amounts to (I hope this isn't an oversimplification) is that if Alice and Bob use different pure states, |\phi\rangle and |\psi\rangle, say, to describe the same system, then one or the other (or both) of them is wrong. This is sort of obvious, because different states predict different probabilities. So if you can repeatedly place a system into the same state, then you can compile statistics that will rule out one state or the other. What PBR shows is that by using tensored states, you can distinguish between the two states in one measurement, so it's not necessary to compile statistics. That makes the conclusion more stark, but I don't find the conclusion itself very strange.
 
  • #181
vanhees71 said:
I'll have a look at it. I take the publication in Nature as the final word on it, or is it rather v3 of the arXiv preprint the final word?

https://arxiv.org/abs/1111.3328
The publication in Nature and arXiv v3 are essentially the same. If there are any differences at all, they are not substantial.
 
  • #182
stevendaryl said:
I agree with you, but it seems to me that bringing up entanglement swapping just complicates things without adding any new feature. (Does it?)

Entanglement is a feature of the quantum state of a composite system. So asking whether entanglement is objective is a special case of asking whether the state is objective. The usual EPR experiment already raises that question. Initially, Bob's photon is described (by both Alice and Bob) as unpolarized, having the density matrix \frac{1}{2} |H\rangle \langle H| + \frac{1}{2} |V\rangle \langle V|. After Alice measures her photon, but before Bob finds out her result, Alice would describe Bob's photon as in the state |H\rangle \langle H|, while Bob would continue to use the unpolarized state.
Yes, and that's what's found in real-world experiments. If that was not the case, QT was wrong, which it is not according to the empirical facts. Bob will just see an ensemble of unpolarized photons. If, according to A's result, he looks only at the sub-ensemble where she found V for her photon, he'll find in all cases H. The choice of this sub-ensemble is, however only possible after A shared her result with B, and that takes at least the speed-of-light signal travel time to provide that information. This notion of states is, of course, purely epistemic. With an ontic meaning you'd run into the causality trouble and it would indeed be inconsistent since A associates another state than B, but in the ensemble interpretation the two states refer to different ensembles (either the whole ensemble if B didn't take notice of A's measurement or the partial ensemble where A measured V, and it's predicted that the 2nd ensemble has about only 1/2 the size as the 1st (full) ensemble).

Generally, I think physical theory is silent about ontics. It describes the outcome of observations/measurements but doesn't provide an "ontology". An electron is described in physics entirely by it's properties (mass, several charges of the standard model; in short it's a charged lepton with mass ##m_e \simeq 0.511 \; \text{MeV}/c^2##), but the Standard Model doesn't tell you what it "really is" in any sense beyond these properties.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #183
vanhees71 said:
Yes, and that's what's found in real-world experiments. If that was not the case, QT was wrong, which it is not according to the empirical facts. Bob will just see an ensemble of unpolarized photons.

Earlier, you were saying that by "state" you always mean something objective. But if Alice describes a photon as horizontally polarized, and Bob describes it as unpolarized, then either one of them is wrong, or the states are subjective.

[Note: you seem to be using ontic/epistemic for what I was calling objective/subjective]
 
  • #184
stevendaryl said:
Well, the conclusion of PBR is not that mysterious to me. What it really amounts to (I hope this isn't an oversimplification) is that if Alice and Bob use different pure states, |\phi\rangle and |\psi\rangle, say, to describe the same system, then one or the other (or both) of them is wrong. This is sort of obvious, because different states predict different probabilities. So if you can repeatedly place a system into the same state, then you can compile statistics that will rule out one state or the other. What PBR shows is that by using tensored states, you can distinguish between the two states in one measurement, so it's not necessary to compile statistics. That makes the conclusion more stark, but I don't find the conclusion itself very strange.
But as should be very clear, in the standard way of the ensemble interpretation as I've explained in several previous postings in this thread now, there is no contradiction between any probabilities. Using the definitions in my previous posting #182: Both Alice and Bob predict 50% V-polarized photons at Bob's place for the "full ensemble" and both Alice and Bob also predict 100% H-polarized photon for the subensemble, where Alice measured her photon to be V-polarized, supposed Bob is able to choose the subensemble based on Alice's information, which he can not get instantaneously but at most with a signal of the speed of light from Alice. So there is not contradiction whatsoever, it's only important to which preparation procedure/ensembles you refer to in subsequent measurements.
 
  • #185
stevendaryl said:
Earlier, you were saying that by "state" you always mean something objective. But if Alice describes a photon as horizontally polarized, and Bob describes it as unpolarized, then either one of them is wrong, or the states are subjective.

[Note: you seem to be using ontic/epistemic for what I was calling objective/subjective]
No, there is no contradiction between the association of states. You choose to look at either the full or a specific subensemble (see postings #182+#184). The association of the state for each of these ensembles is unambiguous (to use another word than objective/subjective now).
 
  • #186
vanhees71 said:
No, there is no contradiction between the association of states. You choose to look at either the full or a specific subensemble (see postings #182+#184). The association of the state for each of these ensembles is unambiguous (to use another word than objective/subjective now).

You want to talk about ensembles, but an EPR experiment makes a prediction about single events: If (with correlated photons) Alice measures her photon to be horizontally polarized along an axis, then it is certain that Bob will measure his photon to be horizontally polarized along that axis.
 
  • #187
stevendaryl said:
You want to talk about ensembles, but an EPR experiment makes a prediction about single events: If (with correlated photons) Alice measures her photon to be horizontally polarized along an axis, then it is certain that Bob will measure his photon to be horizontally polarized along that axis.
Yes, and that's why Bob gets 100% H-polarized photons for the according subensemble. You cannot test the probabilistic predictions without ensembles. How else do you want to test it? If once you measure that Bob finds a H-polarized photon when Alice found her photon to be V-polarized (which of course you will for any single event in this situation) it doesn't tell you anything about whether the probabilistic prediction is right, but you have to repeat the experiment very often (also to get the desired minimal signficance level (like ##5 \sigma##)).
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #188
Demystifier said:
The "collapse" as mere update is consistent with locality. But you open the possibility that collapse can be something more than that, in which case it is not consistent with locality. I think you confuse the readers by not always being explicit about which "collapse" do you have in mind.

By locality, vanhees71 means "locality of interactions". If we are in the minimal interpretation, the "locality of interactions" enforces no superluminal signalling. Collapse, whether physical or not, is consistent with locality of interactions for two reasons.

1) In the minimal interpretation, strictly speaking locality of interactions refers to the form of the Hamiltonian. The collapse (physical or not) does not affect the Hamiltonian, so collapse does not affect locality of interactions.

2) In the minimal interpretation, locality of interactions in the Hamiltonian enforces no superluminal signalling ("locality"). Collapse (physical or not) does not permit superluminal signalling, so collapse is consistent with locality.

3) For collapse to be inconsistent with locality, one must mean something more than locality in the minimal interpretation. One presumably means classical relativistic causality. I suspect that this is what vanhees71 means when he says collapse is inconsistent with locality of interactions - he must be taking the Hamiltonian to be real, and obeying classical relativistic causality. He may even be thinking of the action, which for a bosonic theory has the same form as classical relativistic theories. Collapse, taken to be physical, is certainly inconsistent with this form of locality. However, it is not correct to object to collapse for this reason, since Bell's theorem guarantess that classical relativistic causality is dead.

If vanhees71 were truly using a minimal interpretation, locality would have the meanings in (1) and (2). However, I believe he is using locality in the sense of (3), which means he is actually breaking from the minimal interpretation.
 
  • #189
vanhees71 said:
Yes, and that's why Bob gets 100% H-polarized photons for the according subensemble. You cannot test the probabilistic predictions without ensembles.

If the prediction is that Alice and Bob will get the same result for the same polarization, then a single run is sufficient to falsify it. I think that bringing up ensembles is a red herring.
 
  • Like
Likes Jilang and Heinera
  • #190
atyy said:
By locality, vanhees71 means "locality of interactions". If we are in the minimal interpretation, the "locality of interactions" enforces no superluminal signalling. Collapse, whether physical or not, is consistent with locality of interactions for two reasons.

1) In the minimal interpretation, strictly speaking locality of interactions refers to the form of the Hamiltonian. The collapse (physical or not) does not affect the Hamiltonian, so collapse does not affect locality of interactions.

2) In the minimal interpretation, locality of interactions in the Hamiltonian enforces no superluminal signalling ("locality"). Collapse (physical or not) does not permit superluminal signalling, so collapse is consistent with locality.

3) For collapse to be inconsistent with locality, one must mean something more than locality in the minimal interpretation. One presumably means classical relativistic causality. I suspect that this is what vanhees71 means when he says collapse is inconsistent with locality of interactions - he must be taking the Hamiltonian to be real, and obeying classical relativistic causality. He may even be thinking of the action, which for a bosonic theory has the same form as classical relativistic theories. Collapse, taken to be physical, is certainly inconsistent with this form of locality. However, it is not correct to object to collapse for this reason, since Bell's theorem guarantess that classical relativistic causality is dead.

If vanhees71 were truly using a minimal interpretation, locality would have the meanings in (1) and (2). However, I believe he is using locality in the sense of (3), which means he is actually breaking from the minimal interpretation.
Well, now it seems as if the difference in our opinion is rather whether you consider the interaction of the photon with the measurement device to be within relativistic QFT (which I do, just to be clear) or not. If you agree that this interaction is described within relativistic QFT anything physical "real" "ontic" that can happen in a causal sense must be due to local interactions between the photon and the measurement device.

If one disagrees with that (as do some flavors of the Copenhagen interpretation), and there are "two kinds of dynamics", i.e., a quantum dynamics described by the Hamiltonian and the dynamics describing interactions of measured systems with measurement devices, then indeed QT was incomplete as claimed by EPR.

I don't see any evidence in the literature that quantum-optical elements (like polarizers and photodetectors needed in the here discussed experiments) do not behave as expected when QED is applied.
 
  • #191
stevendaryl said:
If the prediction is that Alice and Bob will get the same result for the same polarization, then a single run is sufficient to falsify it. I think that bringing up ensembles is a red herring.
That's true. If you have perfect measurements, then a single contradiction is enough to disprove a prediction of a probability to be 100%, but a single agreement doesn't prove anything, and that's the point here!
 
  • Like
Likes Heinera
  • #192
vanhees71 said:
If one disagrees with that (as do some flavors of the Copenhagen interpretation), and there are "two kinds of dynamics", i.e., a quantum dynamics described by the Hamiltonian and the dynamics describing interactions of measured systems with measurement devices, then indeed QT was incomplete as claimed by EPR.

The hypothesis that there are these two kinds of dynamics is consistent with our observations. The alternative assumption that there is only one kind of dynamics, that described by the hamiltonian, may also be consistent with our observations, but it seems very complicated to actually demonstrate that. The interpretation that you seem to prefer seems operational indistinguishable from the 2-kinds approach, while your comments about locality seem to be about the 1-kind approach. If you are treating measurements as special (probabilities are only associated with measurement results, not with other kinds of interactions), then it seems to me that you're doing the 2-kinds approach.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #193
vanhees71 said:
Well, now it seems as if the difference in our opinion is rather whether you consider the interaction of the photon with the measurement device to be within relativistic QFT (which I do, just to be clear) or not. If you agree that this interaction is described within relativistic QFT anything physical "real" "ontic" that can happen in a causal sense must be due to local interactions between the photon and the measurement device.

If one disagrees with that (as do some flavors of the Copenhagen interpretation), and there are "two kinds of dynamics", i.e., a quantum dynamics described by the Hamiltonian and the dynamics describing interactions of measured systems with measurement devices, then indeed QT was incomplete as claimed by EPR.

I don't see any evidence in the literature that quantum-optical elements (like polarizers and photodetectors needed in the here discussed experiments) do not behave as expected when QED is applied.
I also believe that there are two kinds of dynamics. The standard quantum "Hamiltonian" dynamics governs the behaviour of ensembles, but it says almost nothing at the individual level. At the individual level, we need a different kind of dynamics. The Bell theorem implies that individual dynamics must be non-local.

The literature on quantum-optical elements concentrates on analysis of the ensemble properties, so it cannot see any evidence for individual dynamics. This is like trying to understand the dynamics of the ball in the roulette wheel by analyzing the statistics of ocurence of the numbers 0-36 in the roulette game.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and atyy
  • #194
vanhees71 said:
Well, now it seems as if the difference in our opinion is rather whether you consider the interaction of the photon with the measurement device to be within relativistic QFT (which I do, just to be clear) or not. If you agree that this interaction is described within relativistic QFT anything physical "real" "ontic" that can happen in a causal sense must be due to local interactions between the photon and the measurement device.

If one disagrees with that (as do some flavors of the Copenhagen interpretation), and there are "two kinds of dynamics", i.e., a quantum dynamics described by the Hamiltonian and the dynamics describing interactions of measured systems with measurement devices, then indeed QT was incomplete as claimed by EPR.

I don't see any evidence in the literature that quantum-optical elements (like polarizers and photodetectors needed in the here discussed experiments) do not behave as expected when QED is applied.

Yes, I don't believe that the QM Hamiltonian describes the interaction between the quantum system and the measuring device. I use the "two kinds of dynamics" Copenhagen, which is what I call the minimal interpretation. This does not mean that polarizers or photodetectors are not described by QED. Rather it means that when we describe polarizers, then something else is the measuring device that measures the polarizer.

If you treat the interactions of QFT as physical or real or ontic, then won't you contradict the Bell theorem, which (roughly) says that reality is nonlocal?

Also, if you have a Hamiltonian for the whole universe, then won't you have a wave function of the universe?
 
  • #195
stevendaryl said:
I agree with you, but it seems to me that bringing up entanglement swapping just complicates things without adding any new feature. (Does it?)

Yes, it's kind of a special case, I agree.

What I find interesting about the entanglement-swapping (and the GHZ projection) is that the projection is onto one of these 'holistic' states that Ken talks about. It's kind of interesting (well to me at least) that a local measurement can affect (apparently instantaneously) the physical properties (the entanglement) of two other objects that are remote from one another, and remote from the measurement. So it's not much of a 'new' feature, it's just a more interesting one to my mind than polarization.

It also calls into question, again in my mind, what it is we actually mean by entanglement. I really can't make a lot of sense out of the knowledge/information update approach to QM when it comes to entanglement. Our physical knowledge about something has to be described as some non-separable vector in a tensor product Hilbert space? What does that even mean? Yet we're happy to describe entanglement as a real, objective, property - and, curiously, this is actually reflected in the maths - but this maths doesn't represent anything physically real - just our state of knowledge? Don't buy it myself.

I confess that I'm kind of old-fashioned in my approach to QM - much happier thinking of the 'state' as at least partially descriptive of some real thing (with some possible subjective element) - measurements are done, the state collapses, all the usual. I do, however, recognize that this isn't entirely wonderful for a relativistically consistent interpretation though. So neither the much-derided ontic, or the epistemic interpretations make total sense to me.

I'm old-fashioned and prejudiced - what can I say? :frown:
 
  • #196
Demystifier said:
The Bell theorem implies that individual dynamics must be non-local.

Is it correct to say that order of measurement results here depend on measurement setting there ?
 
  • #197
Is the PBR theorem really relevant for MEI or similar? According to Scott Aaronson at least, it isn't: http://www.scottaaronson.com/papers/getreal.pdf

"if you adhere to the shut-up-and-calculate philosophy or the Copenhagen interpretation (which I think of as shut-up-and-calculate minus the shutting-up part) then the PBR result shouldn’t trouble you. You don’t have an ontology: you consider it uninteresting or unscientific to discuss reality before measurement. For you, ψ is indeed an encoding of human knowledge, but it’s merely knowledge about the probabilities of various measurement outcomes, not about the state of the world before someone measures."

The theorem supposedly only attacks the psi-epistemic WITH underlying ontology camps.
 
  • #198
Ken G said:
If we think of connectivity of space as important for concepts like nonlocality, and if we interpret entanglement as fundamentally an issue about the holism of systems, then the article seems to be suggesting that our discussion about nonlocality vs. holism has an interesting duality as well: nonlocality in the bulk is dual to holism on the boundary. Put differently, the idea in the article is that the space in the bulk is in some sense "due to" entanglement on the boundary, such that space is "made of entanglement", as they like to say.

I don't suppose you have any idea why long-range correlations would play a role in keeping space connected? That sort of maths is just too advanced for me.

But anyway I like this idea that holism is the default, and phenomenological separability means that something has gone wrong and we have to figure out why.
 
  • #199
Quantum entanglement is empiricaly demonstrated to be real. However we can never be absolutely sure. I guess anyone is invited to prove it wrong. Somewere might be an error or a different mechanism, but that is extremely unlikely.
Any demonstration must be logical, and this one it is. The problem is that the consequences are ridiculous or extremely hard to believe, but it doesn't mean they can't be correct.
For example, instant coordination between particles can suggest a different dimension for the wave function and aloso shared wave function.
Consciousness collapsing a wave function is way more ridiculous, very close to illogical.
 
  • #200
ddd123 said:
I don't suppose you have any idea why long-range correlations would play a role in keeping space connected? That sort of maths is just too advanced for me.
The math is apparently "tensor networks", which I know nothing about but I'm guessing its' 5 years of study before you have a clue.
But anyway I like this idea that holism is the default, and phenomenological separability means that something has gone wrong and we have to figure out why.
Yes, I like that too, so I appreciate our discussion to help bring this out.
 
Back
Top