pellman said:
Let me elaborate a bit further.
One can write down a field version of the Schrodinger theory. In the usual QM theory there is a distinct Hilbert space for a system of 1 particle, a space for 2 particles, etc. So you just use the union of all these spaces. (Nevermind differences of spin, charge, etc. Assuming identical particles here.) You wind up with an anihilation operator which obeys the single-particle Schrodinger equation (well, it's not quite that simple if you have an interaction potential.) That's your quantized field. The creation operator is the Hermitian of the anihilation operator. These two operators have equal-time commutators proportional delta functions, etc.
You don't gain anything by doing this since the states of different particle number remain orthogonal (no actual pair-creation or pair-annihilation). It's just regular old QM in field theory form.
And you can also then write down a Lagrangian for this field.
Or, heck, you can just write down a Lagrangian which yields the single-particle Schrodinger equation. Same thing.
This Lagrangian can be viewed http://books.google.com/books?id=XYc-YajwVuoC&pg=PA214&lpg=PA214&dq=schrodinger+lagrangian&source=web&ots=05qLzoAGm1&sig=wEtEz7nEsbvXroEwjwPtPGo3QvA#PPA216,M1, equation 10.41 Sorry, I haven't got this Tex thing down yet.
So the question is: is there a symmetry transformation of this Lagrangian which is associated with the conserved probability current, a la Noether's theorem?
Or, if you don't like this Schrodinger Lagrangian thing, I would be interested in the same question for the Dirac equation. The conserved current is discussed here.
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Dirac_equation#Adjoint_Equation_and_Dirac_Current Is there a symmetry of the Dirac Lagrangian density which is associated with this current?
Hi pellman,
I understand well the reasons for your questions and your confusion. I was in the same state of confusion regarding QFT some 11-12 years ago before I read Weinberg's book and his earlier works, in particular
S. Weinberg, "The quantum theory of massless particles", in
Lectures on Particles
and Field Theory, vol. 2, edited by S. Deser and K. W. Ford,
(Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, 1964)
which was the real eye-opener for me.
I strongly recommend you to find Weinberg's book and to study it. Then you would understand that questions you are asking don't make a lot of sense. Quantum fields have nothing to do with wave functions of particles. Equations satisfied by quantum fields (Klein-Gordon, Dirac, etc.) are
not analogs of the Schroedinger equation. It doesn't make physical sense to write a Lagrangian from which the Schroedinger equation can be derived. Yes, you can do that mathematically, but this would contradict the fundamental logic of introducing quantum fields in the theory of multiparticle systems.
Quantum fields (and everything that go along with them - the Lagrangians, wave equations, etc.) are not useful in the theory of free non-interacting particles. Such a theory can be constructed in a simple non-controversial way without using the concept of fields at all. This can be done in a series of steps:
(1) Define Hilbert spaces of single particles as spaces of irreducible unitary representations of the Poincare group (see Wigner)
(2) Define multi-particle Hilbert spaces as tensor products of 1-particle spaces in (1).
(3) Define the Fock space as a direct sum of n-particle spaces, where n varies from 0 to infinity.
(4) Define particle creation and annihilation operators in the Fock space. Any (operator of) observable of physical interest now can be written as a polynomial in the particle creation and annihilation operators. Note that creation and annihilation operators can be written in any convenient representation. It is conventional to write them in the momentum-spin representation, but you can also write them in the (Newton-Wigner) position-spin representation.
(5) In the Fock space it is not difficult to define operators of particle observables (momentum, position, spin, etc.), corresponding eigenvectors, wave functions of multiparticle states (as expansion coefficients of the state vector in eigenvectors of particle observables). Moreover, it is easy to define the non-interacting unitary representation U_g^0 of the Poincare group which determines how operators of observables and wave functions transform with respect to time translations, space translations, rotations, and boosts. As usual, time translations of wave functions can be expressed as solutions of the Schroedinger equation.
The theory of free particles outlined above does not require any involvement of fields. According to Weinberg, quantum fields are necessary, if we want to consider inter-particle interactions. The theory of interacting particles is different from the above theory (1) - (5) only in one aspect: The unitary representation of the Poincare group U_g should be different from the non-interacting representation U_g^0 constructed above. The fundamental question is how to construct U_g so that all physical requirements (i.e., relativistic invariance, cluster separability, the possibility of particle creation and absorption, etc.) are satisfied? Weinberg shows how to do that by using certain formal linear combinations of particle creation and annihilation operators called "quantum fields".
In this approach the fundamental physical ingredients are particles and their interactions. Quantum fields are formal mathematical objects which do not have any physical interpretation and do not correspond to anything observed in nature. Their only role is to assist in derivation of particle interaction operators. The same formal status is assigned to all the machinery that goes with quantum fields: Lagrangians, wave equations, canonical quantization, gauge invariance, etc.
Surely, this is not how QFT is presented in most traditional textbooks. But I suggest you to stick to the Weinberg's interpretation. In my opinion, this is the only correct interpretation of QFT. The (legitimate) questions that you are asking don't have good answers in the traditional approach, but they simply don't make sense in the Weinberg's approach.
Eugene.