touqra
- 284
- 0
What is a pure state and a mixed state?
touqra said:What is a pure state and a mixed state?
touqra said:What is a pure state and a mixed state?
koantum said:First of all: what is a state? It's a probability algorithm. We use it to assign probabilities to possible measurement outcomes on the basis of actual measurement outcomes (usually called "preparations"). A measurement is complete if it yields the maximum possible amount of information about the system at hand. A state is pure if it assigns probabilities on the basis of the outcome of a complete measurement. Otherwise it is mixed.
What you write is a correct view from the "information" (epistemological) point of view. Personally, I like to see something more than just a statement about knowledge, but I agree that this is a possible viewpoint which is endorsed by some. In that viewpoint, the only "state" we talk about, is a state of our knowledge about nature, and not an ontological state of nature.
touqra said:What is a pure state and a mixed state?
koantum said:What is the proper (mathematically rigorous and philosophically sound) way of dealing with a fuzzy observable? It is to assign probabilities to the possible outcomes of a measurement of this observable. But if the quantum-mechanical probability assignments serve to describe an objective fuzziness, then they are assignments of objective probabilities.
So the fact that quantum mechanics deals with probabilities does not imply that it is an epistemic theory. If it deals with objective probabilities, then it is an ontological theory.
There is no need to read a statistical physics course. Quantum mechanics represents the possible outcomes to which its algorithms assign probabilities by the subspaces of a vector space, it represents its pure probability algorithms by 1-dimensional subspaces of the same vector space, and it represents its mixed algorithms by probability distributions over pure algorithms. Hence the name "mixed".dextercioby said:A pure state: it has a simple mathematical meaning, namely a point in the projective Hilbert space of the system, or, if you prefer, a unidimensional linear subspace (a.k.a. unit ray, or simply ray, if there's no room for confusions) in the Hilbert space associated to any quantum system.
A mixed state: well, if you read any statistical physics course under the title "Virtual statistical ensembles in quantum statistics" you'll get a very good idea on it.
Please explain how this would imply what you think it implies. State your assumptions so that I can point out either that they are wrong or that I do not share them.vanesch said:There's a hic with this view, because it would imply that there are a set of observables (spanning a phase space) over which quantum theory generates us a Kolmogorov probability distribution, as such fixing entirely the probabilities of the outcomes of all POTENTIAL measurements.
koantum said:Please explain how this would imply what you think it implies. State your assumptions so that I can point out either that they are wrong or that I do not share them.
vanesch said:Some claim therefor that the true quantum state of a system is given by rho, and not by an element in hilbert space. However, this leads to other problems...
Dear vanesh,vanesch said:Well, you are correct in stating that, given a wavefunction, or a mixed state, AND GIVEN A CHOICE OF COMMUTING OBSERVABLES, that the wavefunction/density matrix generates a probability distribution over the set of these observables. As such, one might say - as you do - that these variables are "fuzzy" quantities, and that they are correctly described by the generated probability function.
However, if I make ANOTHER choice of commuting observables, which is not compatible with the previous set, I will compute a different probability distribution for these new observables. No problem as of yet.
But what doesn't work always is to consider the UNION of these two sets of observables, and require that there is an overall probability distribution that will describe this union. As such, one cannot say that the observable itself "has" a probability distribution, independent of whether we were going to pick it out or not in our set of commuting observables...
So in that sense, I wanted to argue that it is not possible to claim that every POTENTIAL observable is a "fuzzy quantity" that is correctly described by a probability distribution - which - I assumed in that case, must be existing independent of the SET of (commuting) observables that we are going to select for the experiment.
koantum said:There are basically two kinds of interpretation, those that acknowledge the central role played by measurements in standard axiomatizations of quantum mechanics, and those that try to sweep it under the rug. As a referee of a philosophy-of-science journal once put it to me, "to solve [the measurement problem] means to design an interpretation in which measurement processes are not different in principle from ordinary physical interactions.''
To my way of thinking, this definition of "solving the measurement problem" is the reason why as yet no sensible solution has been found. Those who acknowledge the importance of measurements, on the other hand, appear think of probabilities as inherently subjective and therefore cannot comprehend the meaning of objective probabilities. Yet it should be perfectly obvious that quantum-mechanical probabilities cannot be subjective. Subjective (that is, ignorance) probabilities disappear when all relevant facts are taken into account (which in many cases is practically impossible). The uncertainty principle however guarantees that quantum-mechanical probabilities cannot be made to disappear.
Mermin in fact believes that the mysteries of quantum mechanics can be reduced to the single puzzle posed by the existence of objective probabilities, and I think that this is correct.
Rather, those who consider quantum theory as a universal theory (in your sense) feel the necessity of adding an extra thing: surreal particle trajectories (Bohm), nonlinear modifications of the dynamics (Ghirardi, Rimini, and Weber or Pearle), the so-called eigenstate-eigenvalue link (van Fraassen), the modal semantical rule (Dieks), and what have you.vanesh said:I would classify these two different views differently. I'd say that those who consider quantum theory as a "partial" theory have no problem adding an extra thing, called measurement process, while those that want to take on the view that quantum theory is a *universal* physical theory, cannot accept such a process.
I don’t know of any axiomatic formulation of quantum mechanics in which measurements do not play a fundamental role. What axioms are you talking about?if quantum theory is to be universal (that means that its axioms apply to everything in the world - necessarily a reductionist viewpoint of course)…
In a theory that rejects evolving quantum states the question "to collapse or not to collapse?" doesn’t arise. What generates this "(apparent?) transition" is one of several http://thisquantumworld.com/pseudo.htm" arising from the the unwarranted and unverifiable postulate of quantum state evolution.The ONLY probabilistic part of the usual application of quantum theory is when one has to make a transition to a classical end state (the so-called collapse). Whatever it is that generates this (apparent?) transition…
So you accept an objectively random process whose dynamics quantum theory cannot describe? What happened to your claim that… it surely is an objectively random process - but of which the dynamics is NOT described by quantum theory itself (it being a DETERMINISTIC theory concerning the wave function evolution).
What IS valid (and universally so) is that quantum mechanics correlates measurement outcomes. The really interesting question about quantum mechanics is: how can a theory that correlates measurement outcomes be fundamental and complete? Preposterous, isn’t it? If people had spend the same amount of time and energy trying to answer this question, rather than disputing whether quantum states collapse or don’t collapse, we would have gotten somewhere by now.when you want to give an interpretation of a theory, you cannot start by claiming that it is NOT universally valid (without saying also, then, what IS valid).
There is no way, if reality is an evolving ray in Hilbert space, to even define subsystems, measurements, observers, interactions, etc. Also, it has never been explained why, if reality is an evolving ray in Hilbert space, certain mathematical expressions of the quantum formalism should be interpreted as probabilities. So far every attempt to explain this has proved circular. The decoherence program in particular relies heavily on reduced density operators, and the operation by which these are obtained - partial tracing - presupposes Born's probability rule. Obviously you don’t have this problem is the quantum formalism is fundamentally a probability algorithm.There's no way, if quantum theory is to be universally applied, to copy a quantum state to a *classical* state of the body…
koantum said:Rather, those who consider quantum theory as a universal theory (in your sense) feel the necessity of adding an extra thing: surreal particle trajectories (Bohm), nonlinear modifications of the dynamics (Ghirardi, Rimini, and Weber or Pearle), the so-called eigenstate-eigenvalue link (van Fraassen), the modal semantical rule (Dieks), and what have you.
The only thing we are sure about is that quantum mechanics is an algorithm for assigning probabilities to possible measurement outcomes on the basis of actual outcomes. If measurements are an "extra thing", what is quantum mechanics without measurements? Nothing at all!
I don’t know of any axiomatic formulation of quantum mechanics in which measurements do not play a fundamental role. What axioms are you talking about?
Whether you believe in unitary evolution between measurements or unitary evolution always makes no difference to me. I reject the whole idea of an evolving quantum state, not just because it is unscientific by Popper's definition (since the claim that it exists is unfalsifiable) but because it prevents us from recognizing the true ontological implications of the quantum formalism (which are pointed out at http://thisquantumworld.com" ). The dependence on time of the quantum-mechanical probability algorithms (states, wave functions) is a dependence on the times of measurements, not the time dependence of an evolving state.
In a theory that rejects evolving quantum states the question "to collapse or not to collapse?" doesn’t arise. What generates this "(apparent?) transition" is one of several http://thisquantumworld.com/pseudo.htm" arising from the the unwarranted and unverifiable postulate of quantum state evolution.
So you accept an objectively random process whose dynamics quantum theory cannot describe? What happened to your claim that
What IS valid (and universally so) is that quantum mechanics correlates measurement outcomes. The really interesting question about quantum mechanics is: how can a theory that correlates measurement outcomes be fundamental and complete? Preposterous, isn’t it? If people had spend the same amount of time and energy trying to answer this question, rather than disputing whether quantum states collapse or don’t collapse, we would have gotten somewhere by now.
There is no way, if reality is an evolving ray in Hilbert space, to even define subsystems, measurements, observers, interactions, etc. Also, it has never been explained why, if reality is an evolving ray in Hilbert space, certain mathematical expressions of the quantum formalism should be interpreted as probabilities. So far every attempt to explain this has proved circular. The decoherence program in particular relies heavily on reduced density operators, and the operation by which these are obtained - partial tracing - presupposes Born's probability rule. Obviously you don’t have this problem is the quantum formalism is fundamentally a probability algorithm.
An informed choice should weigh the absurdities spawned by the second option against the merits of the first.
Not too crazy. Borrowing the words of Niels Bohr, crazy but not crazy enough to be true.vanesch said:I repeated often that the ONLY objection to an MWI/many minds view is "naah, too crazy"...
What about your own emphasis that classical physics can be formulated without reference to measurements, while quantum mechanics cannot?vanesh said:This can be said about any scientific theory.The only thing we are sure about is that quantum mechanics is an algorithm for assigning probabilities to possible measurement outcomes on the basis of actual outcomes. If measurements are an "extra thing", what is quantum mechanics without measurements? Nothing at all!
Let me tell you in a few steps why we all use a complex vector space. (I can give you the details later if you are interested.) I use this approach when I teach quantum mechanics to higher secondary and undergraduate student.1) the Hilbert space, spanned by the eigenvectors of "a complete set of observables" (which is nothing else but an enumeration of the degrees of freedom of the system, and the values they can take)
2) the unitary evolution (the derivative of it being the Hamiltonian)
You are right of course that there is a statement that links what is "observed" with this mathematical state - but such a statement must be made in ALL physical theories. If you read that statement as: "it is subjectively experienced that..." you're home.
Which is exactly what I do! Newton famously refused to make up a story purporting to explain how, by what mechanism or physical process, matter acts on matter. While the (Newtonian) gravitational action depends on the simultaneous positions of the interacting objects, the electromagnetic action of matter on matter is retarded. This made it possible to transmogrify the algorithm for calculating the electromagnetic effects of matter on matter into a physical mechanism or process by which matter acts on matter.You should then also reject the idea of an evolving classical state, or the existence of a classical electrical field…
Physicists are, at bottom, a naive breed, forever trying to come to terms with the 'world out there' by methods which, however imaginative and refined, involve in essence the same element of contact as a well-placed kick. (B.S. DeWitt and R.N. Graham, Resource letter IQM-1 on the interpretation of quantum mechanics, AJP 39, pp. 724-38, 1971.)
This is what you are led to conclude because you don’t have a decent characterization of macroscopic objects.vanesh said:… or even the existence of other persons you're not observing.
You find a deterministic theory of everything inspiring? Perhaps this is because you want to believe in your omniscience-in-principle: you want to feel as if you know What Exists and how it behaves. To entertain this belief you must limit Reality to mathematically describable states and processes. This is in part a reaction to outdated religious doctrines (it is better to believe in our potential omniscience than in the omnipotence of someone capable of creating a mess like this world and thinking he did a great job) and in part the sustaining myth of the entire scientific enterprise (you had better believe that what you are trying to explain can actually be explained with the means at your disposal).It doesn't lead to a very inspiring picture of the world ; it is essentially the "information" world view, where scientific (and other) theories are nothing else but organizing schemes of successive observations and no description of an actual reality.
How convenient. What I experience is not part of physics. How does this square with your claimed universality of the quantum theory? And what I do not experience – Hilbert space vectors, wave functions, and suchlike – is part of physics. How silly!The random process, in the MWI view, is entirely subjective ; it is not part of the physics, but of what you happen to subjectively experience.
As long as you mix up experiences with measurements, you are not getting anywhere.All theory "correlates" subjective experiences (also called measurements)…
I have a somewhat higher regard for "reality". Like Aristotle, I refuse to have it identified with computational devices. ("The so-called Pythagoreans, who were the first to take up mathematics, not only advanced this subject, but saturated with it, they fancied that the principles of mathematics were the principles of all things." - Metaphysics 1-5.)So anybody claiming that one shouldn't say that certain concepts in an explanatory scheme of observations (such as quantum theory, or any scientific theory) are "real" misses the whole point of what "reality" is for: it is for its conceptual simplification !
Chalmers called this the "law of minimization of mystery": quantum mechanics is mysterious, consciousness is mysterious, so maybe they are the same mystery. But mysteries need to be solved, not hidden.I get a weird rule that links my subjective experience to physical reality, but as that is in ANY CASE something weird, it's the place to hide any extra weirdness.
koantum said:Let me tell you in a few steps why we all use a complex vector space. (I can give you the details later if you are interested.) I use this approach when I teach quantum mechanics to higher secondary and undergraduate student.
- "Ordinary" objects have spatial extent (they "occupy" space), are composed of a (large but) finite number of objects that lack spatial extent, and are stable - they neither collapse nor explode the moment they are formed. Thanks to quantum mechanics, we know that the stability of atoms (and hence of "ordinary" objects) rests on the fuzziness (the literal translation of Heisenberg's "Unschärfe") of their internal relative positions and momenta.
[*]The proper way of dealing with a fuzzy observable is to assign probabilities to the possible outcomes of a measurement of this observable.
[*]The classical probability algorithm is represented by a point P in a phase space; the measurement outcomes to which it assigns probabilities are represented by subsets of this space. Because this algorithm only assigns trivial probabilities (1 if P is inside the subset representing an outcome, 0 if P is outside), we may alternatively think of P as describing the state of the system in the classical sense (a collection of possessed properties), regardless of measurements.
[*]To deal with fuzzy observables, we need a probability algorithm that can accommodate probabilities in the whole range between 0 and 1. The straightforward way to do this is to replace the 0 dimensional point P by a 1 dimensional line L, and to replace the subsets by the subspaces of a vector space. (Because of the 1-1 correspondence between subspaces and projectors, we may equivalently think of outcomes as projectors.) We assign probability 1 if L is contained in the subspace representing an outcome, probability 0 if L is orthogonal to it, and a probability 0>p>1 otherwise. (Because this algorithm assigns nontrivial probabilities, it cannot be re-interpreted as a classical state.)
[*]We now have to incorporate a compatibility criterion. It is readily shown (later, if you are in the mood for it) that the outcomes of compatible measurements must correspond to commuting projectors.
[*]Last but not least we require: if the interval C is the union of two disjoint intervals A and B, then the probability of finding the value of an observable in C is the sum of the probabilities of finding it in A or B, respectively.
[*]We now have everything that is needed to prove Gleason's theorem, according to which the probability of an outcome represented by the projector P is the trace of WP, where W (known as the "density operator") is linear, self-adjoint, positive, has trace 1, and satisfies either WW=W (then we call it a "pure state") or WW<W (then we call it "mixed"). (We are back to the topic of this thread!)
At this point we have all the axioms of your list (you missed a few) but with one crucial difference: we know where these axioms come from. We know where quantum mechanics comes from, whereas you haven’t the slightest idea about the origin of your axioms.
This made it possible to transmogrify the algorithm for calculating the electromagnetic effects of matter on matter into a physical mechanism or process by which matter acts on matter.
Later Einstein's theory of gravity made it possible to similarly transmogrify the algorithm for calculating the gravitational effects of matter on matter into a mechanism or physical process.
Let's separate the facts from the fictions (assuming for the moment that facts about the world of classical physics are facts rather than fictions).
Fact is that the calculation of effects can be carried out in two steps:
Fiction is
- Given the distribution and motion of charges, we calculate six functions (the so-called "electromagnetic field"), and given these six functions, we calculate the electromagnetic effects that those charges have on other charges.
- Given the distribution and motion of matter, we calculate the stress-energy tensor, and given the stress-energy tensor, we calculate the gravitational effects that matter here has on matter there.
- that the electromagnetic field is a physical entity in its own right, that it is locally generated by charges here, that it mediates electromagnetic interactions by locally acting on itself, and that it locally acts on charges there;
- that spacetime curvature is a physical entity in its own right, and that it mediates the gravitational action of matter on matter by a similar local process.
koantum said:Let me tell you in a few steps why we all use a complex vector space. (I can give you the details later if you are interested.) I use this approach when I teach quantum mechanics to higher secondary and undergraduate student. ...
Why?The proper way of dealing with a fuzzy observable is to assign probabilities to the possible outcomes of a measurement of this observable.
For one thing, because nobody ever has come up with a different way of dealing with a fuzzy observable. Or am I misinformed? But I should have been more precise: the proper way of dealing with a fuzzy observable O is to assign probabilities to the possible outcomes of an unperformed measurement of O. If no measurement is actually made, all we can say about a quantum system is with what probability this or that outcome would be obtained if the corresponding measurement were made. If the probability is >0 for the possible outcomes v1,v2,v3..., then the value of O is fuzzy in the sense that the propositions "the value of O is vi" (i=1,2,3,...) are neither true nor false but meaningless.Hurkyl said:Why?
And what would that be?This goes directly against what I remember about fuzzy sets and fuzzy logic.
That it's not based at all on probability.And what would that be?
koantum said:the proper way of dealing with a fuzzy observable O is to assign probabilities to the possible outcomes of an unperformed measurement of O. If no measurement is actually made, all we can say about a quantum system is with what probability this or that outcome would be obtained if the corresponding measurement were made. If the probability is >0 for the possible outcomes v1,v2,v3..., then the value of O is fuzzy in the sense that the propositions "the value of O is vi" (i=1,2,3,...) are neither true nor false but meaningless.
An intuitive concept is one thing, a commonsense concept is quite another. Time is an intuitive concept. So is space. Like pink and turquoise, spatial extension is a quale that can only be defined by ostentation - by drawing attention to something of which we are directly aware. While the intuition of space can lend a phenomenal quality to numerical parameters, it cannot be reduced to such parameters.In a complete world picture, there is no room for intuitive and common sense concepts at the foundations…. The exercise consists in building up, WITHOUT USING common sense concepts at the foundations, a mental picture of the world, AND SEE IF OUR COMMON SENSE and less common sense observations can be explained by it.
Agreed. (But then one mustn't sweep under the rug all those data that don’t fit.) In fact, I said something to this effect in several of my papers. Permit me to quote myself:Why is it important to try to derive a complete world picture? Firstly, to see where it fails!
I have found that students (higher secondary and undergraduate) are much happier if I can show them where exactly the quantum formalism comes from and why it has the form that it does, than if I confront them with a set of abstruse axioms and tell them that that's the way it is! What value does an explanation have if it is based on something nobody comprehends? You may call my approach teleological. I ask, what must the laws of physics be like so that the "ordinary" objects which surround us can exist? You stop at the fundamental laws and take them for God-given. If you want to go further and understand a fundamental theory, the teleological (not theological!) approach is the only viable one: explaining why (in the teleological sense) the laws of physics are just so.I think it is already fairly clear here, that there is an appeal to a mixture of intuitive ontological concepts. But an "algorithmic" theory cannot take for granted the ontological existence of any such "ordinary" object: their existence must be DERIVABLE from its fundamental formulation.
It ought to be clear by now that I reject the view that measurements have anything to do with conscious observations. Measurements are presupposed by the quantum formalism since all it does is correlate measurement outcomes. Attempts to make the quantum formalism consistent with the existence of measurements are therefore misconceived. Since it presupposes measurements, it is trivially consistent with their existence. Any notion to the contrary arises from misconceptions that must be identified and eliminated.how does a "measurement apparatus" link to an observable? Does the measurement apparatus have ontological existence? Or does only the observation of the measurement apparatus (by a person?) make sense…
So? In quantum mechanics we have measurement outcomes (possibilities) and an algorithm that assigns to them probabilities.Hurkyl said:probability and possibility theory are distinct theories, and neither is subsumed under the other.
koantum said:An intuitive concept is one thing, a commonsense concept is quite another. Time is an intuitive concept. So is space. Like pink and turquoise, spatial extension is a quale that can only be defined by ostentation - by drawing attention to something of which we are directly aware.
While the intuition of space can lend a phenomenal quality to numerical parameters, it cannot be reduced to such parameters.
If you are not convinced, try to explain to my friend Andy, who lives in a spaceless world, what space is like. Andy is good at maths, so he understands you perfectly if you tell him that it is like the set of all triplets of real numbers. But if you believe that this gives him a sense of the expanse we call space, you are deluding yourself. We can imagine triplets of real numbers as geometrical points embedded in space; he can't. We can interpret the difference between two numbers as the distance between two points; he can't. At any rate, he can't associate with the word "distance" the remoteness it conveys to us.
So without using intuitive concepts at the foundations, you cannot even talk about space (and this should be even more obvious for time).
I'm not saying that you cannot come up with a mathematical construct and call it "space". You can define "self-adjoint operator" = "elephant" and "spectral decomposition" = "trunk", and then you can prove a theorem according to which every elephant has a trunk. But please don’t tell me that this theorem has anything to do with real pachyderms.
Agreed. (But then one mustn't sweep under the rug all those data that don’t fit.) In fact, I said something to this effect in several of my papers. Permit me to quote myself:
Science is driven by the desire to know how things really are. It owes its immense success in large measure to its powerful "sustaining myth" [this is reference to an article by Mermin] - the belief that this can be discovered. Neither the ultraviolet catastrophe nor the spectacular failure of Rutherford's model of the atom made physicists question their faith in what they can achieve. Instead, Planck and Bohr went on to discover the quantization of energy and angular momentum, respectively. If today we seem to have reason to question our "sustaining myth", it ought to be taken as a sign that we are once again making the wrong assumptions, and it ought to spur us on to ferret them out." Anything else should be seen for what it is - a cop-out.
I wrote this in response to Bernard d'Espagnat's claim that without nonlinear modifications of the Schrödinger equation (or similar adulterations of standard quantum mechanics) we cannot go beyond objectivity in the weak sense of inter-subjective agreement. I wrote something similar in response to the claim by Fuchs and Peres (in their opinion piece in Physics Today, March 2000) that QM is an epistemic theory and does not yield a model of a "free-standing" reality.
I have found that students (higher secondary and undergraduate) are much happier if I can show them where exactly the quantum formalism comes from and why it has the form that it does, than if I confront them with a set of abstruse axioms and tell them that that's the way it is! What value does an explanation have if it is based on something nobody comprehends?
You may call my approach teleological. I ask, what must the laws of physics be like so that the "ordinary" objects which surround us can exist? You stop at the fundamental laws and take them for God-given. If you want to go further and understand a fundamental theory, the teleological (not theological!) approach is the only viable one: explaining why (in the teleological sense) the laws of physics are just so.
It ought to be clear by now that I reject the view that measurements have anything to do with conscious observations. Measurements are presupposed by the quantum formalism since all it does is correlate measurement outcomes.
Attempts to make the quantum formalism consistent with the existence of measurements are therefore misconceived. Since it presupposes measurements, it is trivially consistent with their existence. Any notion to the contrary arises from misconceptions that must be identified and eliminated.
So what are measurements? Any event or state of affairs from which the truth or the falsity of a statement about the world can be inferred, qualifies as a measurement, regardless of whether anyone is around to make that inference.
How the "apparatus" links to an observable? It defines it. Consider an electron spin associated with the ket |z+>. What do we know about this spin? All we know is how it behaves in any given measurement context, that is, we know the possible outcomes and we can calculate their probabilities. By defining - and not just defining but realizing - an axis, the setup makes available two possible values; it creates possibilities to which probabilities can be assigned. In the absence of an apparatus that realizes a particular axis, the properties "up" and "down" do not even exist as possibilities. The idea that |z+> represents something as it is, all by itself, rather than as it behaves in possible measurement situations, is completely vacuous.
And the same applies to all quantum states, wave functions, etc.
Does the measurement apparatus have ontological existence? Certainly. Any macroscopic object has, and so has everything that can be inferred from a measurement (as defined above).
That's not how possibility theory works.So? In quantum mechanics we have measurement outcomes (possibilities) and an algorithm that assigns to them probabilities.
Great. Then only one needs to be eliminated.vanesch said:I'd think that there are two ways of doing what you want to do.
This is indeed the most general algorithm but it can be narrowed down (via Gleason's theorem) to the conventional Hilbert space formalism. This is shown in J.M. Jauch, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1968). Also, "compatible" is not defined at will. Once you have the Hilbert space formalism, it is obvious how to define compatibility.One can say that, to each "compatible" (to be defined at will) set of observables corresponds a different probability space, and the observables are then random variables over this space. THIS is the most general random algorithm. The projection of a ray in a vector space is way more restrictive, and I don't see why this must be the case.
I admit that this requirement is not inevitable. As you pointed out, probabilities can depend on measurement contexts; in a different context the same outcome need not have the same probability. In the context of composite systems contextual observables are indeed readily identified, as they are if we allow probability assignments based on earlier and later outcomes using the ABL rule (so named after Aharonov, Bergmann, and Lebowitz) instead of the Born rule, which assigns probabilities on the basis of earlier or later outcomes.Ok, this is an explicit requirement of non-contextuality. Why?
Sorry if I gave the wrong impression. Not a "general scheme, period" but a general scheme for dealing with the objectively fuzzy observables that we need if we want to have "ordinary" objects. We started out with a discussion of objective probabilities, which certainly raises lots of questions. To be able to answer these questions consistently, I have to repudiate more than one accepted prejudice about quantum mechanics.I had the impression you wanted to show that quantum theory is nothing else but a kind of "general scheme of writing down a generator for probability algorithms of observations", but we've made quite some hypotheses along the way!
Whereas non-contextuality is implied by an ontology of self-existent positions (or values of whatever kind), it doesn’t imply such an ontology.the non-contextuality requirement goes against the spirit of denying an ontological status to the "quantity to be measured outside of its measurement"…. [it] REQUIRES THE POSTULATION OF SOME ONTOLOGICAL EXISTENCE OF A QUANTITY INDEPENDENT OF A MEASUREMENT - which is, according to your view, strictly forbidden.
Have you now turned from an Everettic into a Bohmian? How come you seem to be all praise for intuitive concepts when a few moments ago you spurned them? And how is it that "ruler says position 5.4cm" is hard to make sense of for non-Bohmians? I find statements about self-existing positions or "regions of space" harder to make sense of. If I have a detector monitoring the interval from 5.4 to 5.6 (or from 5.40 to 5.41 for that matter) then I know what I am talking about. The detector is needed to realize (make real) this interval or region of space. It makes the property of being in this interval available for attribution. Then it only takes a click to make it "stick" to a particle.BTW, the above illustrates the "economy of concept" that results from postulating an ontology, and the intuitive help it provides. The unrelated statements "ruler says position 5.4cm" and "fine ruler says 5.43cm" which are hard to make any sense of, become suddenly almost trivial concepts when we say that there IS a particle, and that we have tried to find its position using two physical experiments, one with a better resolution than the other.
It might be better to call them visual aids or heuristic tools.Well, these fictions are strong conceptual economies.
I don’t deny that thinking of the electromagnetic field as a tensor sitting at every spacetime point is a powerful visual aid to solving problems in classical electrodynamics. If you only want to use the physics, this is OK. But not if you want to understand it. There just isn’t any way in which one and the same thing can be both a computational tool and a physical entity in its own right. The "classical" habit of transmogrifying computational devices into physical entities is one of the chief reasons why we fail to make sense of the quantum formalism, for in quantum physics the same sleight of hand only produces pseudo-problems and gratuitous solutions.For instance, if I have a static electrostatic field, I'm not really surprised that a charge can accelerate one way or another, but that the DIRECTION of its acceleration at a certain position is always the same: the electric field vector is pointing in one and only one direction ! Now, if I see this as an ALGORITHM, then I don't see, a priori, why suddenly charges could not decide to go a bit in all possible directions as a function of their charge. I can imagine writing myself any algorithm that can do that. But when I physically think of the electric field at a point, I find a natural explanation for this single direction.
As I have pointed out, there are additional factors that narrow down the range of possible algorithms. I never claimed that kind of arbitrariness for the quantum-mechanical algorithm.As an example, let us say that measurement M1 of O takes on the possible outcomes {A,B,C}, with A standing for "O is 1 or 2", B standing for "O is 3 or 4" and C standing for "O is 5 or 6".
Measurement M2 has 6 possible outcomes, {a,b,c,d,e,f}, with a standing for "O is 1", b standing for "O is 2" etc... Now, you want a probability distribution to be assigned to a potential measurement. Fine:
potential measurement M1 of O: p(A) = 0.6, p(B) = 0.4, p(C) = 0.0
Potential measurement M2 of O: p(a) = 0.1, p(b) = 0.1, p(c) = 0.1, p(d)= 0.1, p(e)=0.1, p(f) = 0.5
I have assigned probabilities to the outcomes of measurements M1 and M2. You cannot reproduce this with standard quantum theory, so it is NOT a universal probability-of-potential-compatible-measurements description algorithm.
But I never say that! I wouldn't even consider O in the M1 context to be the same observable as O in the M2 context. Observables are defined by how they are measured, what are the possible outcomes, and what other measurements are made at the same time.And if you now say that p(f) = 0.5 with p(C) is IMPOSSIBLE because "O cannot be at the same time NOT in {5,6} and equal to 6", then you have assigned a measurement-independent reality (ontology) to the quantity O.
I think your hunch is correct. The quantum-mechanical assignments of observable probabilities have nothing to do with belief or plausibility. Let me requote Mermin: "in a non-deterministic world, probability has nothing to do with incomplete knowledge. Quantum mechanics is the first example in human experience where probabilities play an essential role even when there is nothing to be ignorant about."Hurkyl said:That's not how possibility theory works. Evidence theory studies something called a belief measure and a plausibility measure... Of course, this book is not about physical foundations -- it would be talking about subjective probability/possibility, so these comments may not be applicable at all.
My http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/quant-ph/0102103"to d'Espagnat was that his argument for weak objectivity = inter-subjective agreement is a cop-out. (I take it that d'Espagnat's weak objectivity corresponds to what you call solipsism.) My point was that it is our duty as physicists to find what Fuchs and Peres called a "freestanding reality" (which they claim quantum mechanics doesn’t allow). According to d'Espagnat, the elision of the subject is not possible within unadulterated, standard quantum mechanics. I maintain that it is possible. I want a conception of the quantum world to which the conscious subject is as irrelevant as it was to the classical view of the world. It's rather like a game I like to play: let's go find a strongly objective conception of the quantum world that owes nothing to subjects or conscious observations. It is precisely for this reason that I reject the naïve quantum realism that identifies reality with symbols of the mathematical formalism.So at a certain point, you have to link your formal terms in your mathematical formalism to qualia, to subjective experiences. *This* is the essence of the interpretation of ANY theory, classical, quantum or otherwise. It is why I always insist on the fact that there is no fundamental difference between the "measurement problem" in quantum theory, and the one in classical theory ; although the POSTULATE that assigns qualia to formal mathematical elements is simpler in classical theory.
As you can see, we are in perfect agreement even here.this is the point where we seem to differ in opinion: the *hypothesis* (and it will never be anything else, granted) of an objective ontology IS a useful hypothesis.
While I'm certainly no believer in astrology, what you're saying is that your grounds for rejecting astrology are not scientific but metaphysical. That's not good enough for me.With an ontological interpretation, there are grounds to reject astrology; in a purely algorithmic concept, no such grounds exist.
What I show is that if the quantum formalism didn’t have the form that it does then the familiar objects that surround us couldn’t exist. I pointed out that this is a teleological reason, and you are free to deny that teleological reasons are REASONS. But keep in mind that this is the only possible reason a fundamental physical theory can have. Our difference in opinion is that, for me, a mathematical structure that exists without any reason is not an acceptable reason for the existence of everything else.It's a sleight of hand what you present. You DIDN'T present any REASON why the quantum formalism has the form it has, although you seem to claim so.
Absolutely not. I say: stop the naïve transmogrification of mathematical symbols into ontological entities in order to be finally in a position to see the true ontological implications of the quantum formalism.But I (think I) understand your viewpoint, which is "minimalistic", and which is the "shut up and calculate" approach.
As I implied earlier, using physics is not the same as understanding it. Keep in mind that technological applications invariably use approximate laws, the classical laws not being the poorest of them all, and remember Feynman's insistence that "philosophically we are completely wrong with the approximate law" (Feynman's emphasis).How do you use the quantum formalism then in the design of measurement apparatus ?
I could certainly answer these question, but why should I be the first? How do you answer them?What IS a measurement apparatus ? How do you make one ? And how do you determine what it measures?
If, when, and to the extent that it is measured.So the position of a particle "exists"? And its momentum "exists"?
It has a position (or momentum) if, when, and to the extent that its position (or momentum) can be inferred from something that qualifies as a measurement device (see above definition).What does that mean, for a particle to have a position and a momentum?
Nothing is there unless it is indicated by a measurement outcome.Does that mean that my particle IS really there somewhere, and is MOVING in a certain direction?
It has a position if, when, and to the extent that its position is measured. Between measurements (and also beyond the resolution of actual measurements) we can describe the particle only in terms of the probabilities of the possible outcomes of unperformed measurements. The particle isn’t like that "by itself", of course. Nothing can be said without reference to (actual or counterfactual=unperformed) measurements.Does this mean that my particle has an ONTOLOGICALLY EXISTING POSITION at any moment in time (because it could POTENTIALLY be measured)?
NO WAY!But didn't we just give an ONTOLOGICAL EXISTENCE to the wave function then ??
Nonsense.any physical theory that takes on this special status that "measurements are given", makes it impossible to DESIGN measurement apparatus.
Analyze away to your heart's content! You will be using approximate laws, and you won't be bothered about where the underlying laws come from or what their ontological implications are. You, as a professional magician, don’t need to know how the magic formulas work. You just need to use them. Contrariwise, no amount of ontological wisdom will help you even build a mousetrap.As it is my professional activity, I can indicate that this is an annoying feature of a physical theory, that I'm not entitled to analyze the physics of a measurement apparatus!
koantum said:This is indeed the most general algorithm but it can be narrowed down (via Gleason's theorem) to the conventional Hilbert space formalism. This is shown in J.M. Jauch, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1968). Also, "compatible" is not defined at will. Once you have the Hilbert space formalism, it is obvious how to define compatibility.
However, my first aim is to make quantum mechanics comprehensible to bright kids (something that is sorely needed) rather than to hardened quantum mechanicians (for whom there is little hope anymore), and those kids are as happy with this commonsense requirement as they are astonished by the contextualities that arise when systems are combined or when probabilities are assigned symmetrically with respect to time.
My second aim is to find the simplest set of laws that permits the existence of "ordinary" objects, and therefore I require non-contextuality wherever it is possible at all. Nature appears to take the same approach.
Sorry if I gave the wrong impression. Not a "general scheme, period" but a general scheme for dealing with the objectively fuzzy observables that we need if we want to have "ordinary" objects. We started out with a discussion of objective probabilities, which certainly raises lots of questions. To be able to answer these questions consistently, I have to repudiate more than one accepted prejudice about quantum mechanics.
Whereas non-contextuality is implied by an ontology of self-existent positions (or values of whatever kind), it doesn’t imply such an ontology.
Have you now turned from an Everettic into a Bohmian?
How come you seem to be all praise for intuitive concepts when a few moments ago you spurned them? And how is it that "ruler says position 5.4cm" is hard to make sense of for non-Bohmians? I find statements about self-existing positions or "regions of space" harder to make sense of.
When we come to the non-contextuality requirement, I ask my students to assume that p(C)=1, 0<p(A)<1, and 0<p(B)<1. (Recall: A and B are disjoint regions, C is their union, and p(C) is the probability of finding the particle in C if the appropriate measurement is made.) Then I ask: since neither of the detectors monitoring A and B, respectively, is certain to click, how come it is certain that either of them will click? The likely answer: "So what? If p(C)=1 then the particle is in C, and if it isn’t in A (no click), then it is in B (click)." Economy of concept but wrong!
At this point the students are well aware that (paraphrasing Wheeler) no property is a possessed property unless it is a measured property. They have discussed several experiments (Mermin's "simplest version" of Bell's theorem, the experiments of Hardy, GHZ, and ESW) all of which illustrate that assuming self-existent values leads to contradictions. So I ask them again: how come either counter will click if neither counter is certain to click? Bafflement.
Actually the answer is elementary, for implicit in every quantum-mechanical probability assignment is the assumption that a measurement is made. It is always taken for granted that the probabilities of the possible outcomes add up to 1. There is therefore no need to explain this. But there is a lesson here: not even probability 1 is sufficient for "is" or "has". P(C)=1 does not mean that the particle is in C but only that it is certain to be found in C provided that the appropriate measurement is made.
Farewell to Einstein's "elements of reality". Farewell to van Fraassen's eigenstate-eigenvalue link.
You say "there IS a particle". What does this mean? It means there is a conservation law (only in non-relativistic quantum mechanics, though) which tells us that every time we make a position measurement exactly one detector clicks. If every time exactly two detectors click, we say there are two particles.
I don’t deny that thinking of the electromagnetic field as a tensor sitting at every spacetime point is a powerful visual aid to solving problems in classical electrodynamics. If you only want to use the physics, this is OK. But not if you want to understand it. There just isn’t any way in which one and the same thing can be both a computational tool and a physical entity in its own right.
The "classical" habit of transmogrifying computational devices into physical entities is one of the chief reasons why we fail to make sense of the quantum formalism, for in quantum physics the same sleight of hand only produces pseudo-problems and gratuitous solutions.
You also get pseudo-problems in the classical context. Instead of thinking of the electromagnetic field as a tool for calculating the interactions between charges, you think of charges as interacting with the electromagnetic field. How does this interaction work? We have a tool for calculating the interactions between charges, but no tool for calculating the interactions between charges and the electromagnetic field.
Physicists are, at bottom, a naive breed, forever trying to come to terms with the 'world out there' by methods which, however imaginative and refined, involve in essence the same element of contact as a well-placed kick. (B.S. DeWitt and R.N. Graham, Resource letter IQM-1 on the interpretation of quantum mechanics, AJP 39, pp. 724-38, 1971.)
koantum said:(I take it that d'Espagnat's weak objectivity corresponds to what you call solipsism.
) My point was that it is our duty as physicists to find what Fuchs and Peres called a "freestanding reality" (which they claim quantum mechanics doesn’t allow). According to d'Espagnat, the elision of the subject is not possible within unadulterated, standard quantum mechanics. I maintain that it is possible. I want a conception of the quantum world to which the conscious subject is as irrelevant as it was to the classical view of the world. It's rather like a game I like to play: let's go find a strongly objective conception of the quantum world that owes nothing to subjects or conscious observations. It is precisely for this reason that I reject the naïve quantum realism that identifies reality with symbols of the mathematical formalism.
While I'm certainly no believer in astrology, what you're saying is that your grounds for rejecting astrology are not scientific but metaphysical. That's not good enough for me.
What I show is that if the quantum formalism didn’t have the form that it does then the familiar objects that surround us couldn’t exist.
Our difference in opinion is that, for me, a mathematical structure that exists without any reason is not an acceptable reason for the existence of everything else.
and remember Feynman's insistence that "philosophically we are completely wrong with the approximate law" (Feynman's emphasis).
They're just names, and you shouldn't read things into them -- just like the fact the "rational numbers" are not somehow more logical than the "irrational numbers", and the "real numbers" are no more real than the "imaginary numbers".The quantum-mechanical assignments of observable probabilities have nothing to do with belief or plausibility. Let me requote Mermin: "in a non-deterministic world, probability has nothing to do with incomplete knowledge. Quantum mechanics is the first example in human experience where probabilities play an essential role even when there is nothing to be ignorant about."
Hurkyl said:There's no evident reason why the underlying physical measure should be a probability measure -- why isn't it possible, for example, for
P(particle in (0, 2))
to be bigger than
P(particle in (0, 1)) + P(particle in (1, 2))
koantum said:I don’t deny that thinking of the electromagnetic field as a tensor sitting at every spacetime point is a powerful visual aid to solving problems in classical electrodynamics. If you only want to use the physics, this is OK. But not if you want to understand it. There just isn’t any way in which one and the same thing can be both a computational tool and a physical entity in its own right. The "classical" habit of transmogrifying computational devices into physical entities is one of the chief reasons why we fail to make sense of the quantum formalism, for in quantum physics the same sleight of hand only produces pseudo-problems and gratuitous solutions.
You also get pseudo-problems in the classical context. Instead of thinking of the electromagnetic field as a tool for calculating the interactions between charges, you think of charges as interacting with the electromagnetic field. How does this interaction work? We have a tool for calculating the interactions between charges, but no tool for calculating the interactions between charges and the electromagnetic field. With the notable exception of Roger Boscovich, a Croatian physicist and philosopher of the 18th Century, nobody seems to have noticed that local action is as unintelligible as the ability of material objects to act where they are not. Why do we stop worrying once we have transmuted the mystery of action at a distance into the mystery of local action?
According to d'Espagnat, the elision of the subject is not possible within unadulterated, standard quantum mechanics. I maintain that it is possible. I want a conception of the quantum world to which the conscious subject is as irrelevant as it was to the classical view of the world. It's rather like a game I like to play: let's go find a strongly objective conception of the quantum world that owes nothing to subjects or conscious observations. It is precisely for this reason that I reject the naïve quantum realism that identifies reality with symbols of the mathematical formalism.
As a rule, a lucky guess comes first; the reason why it was lucky is found later.hurkyl said:probabilities have achieved a fundamental status in QM because it was doing a good job predicting the outcomes of our frequency-counting experiments... not because there was some theoretical or intuitive reason to do so.
No, there isn’t. Even vanesch agreed with that https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=948676&postcount=16".In MWI, though, there is at least the possibility of deriving probabilities as emergent phenomena, by considering a limit of the resulting states of frequency-counting experiments of increasing length.
If I talk to quantum-state realists, they think I belong to the shut-up-and-calculate (SUC) sect. If I talk to members of this sect, they take me for a quantum-state realist. As far as I am concerned, they are both wrong.vanesch said:I must have completely misunderstood you then.
Gosh, I wish I could do that. But on second thoughts, to what avail?I thought you wanted to show the *naturalness* of the quantum-mechanical formalism, in the sense that you start by stating that we had it wrong all the way, that physical theories do not describe anything ontological, but are algorithms to compute probabilities of measurements, and that that single assumption is sufficient to arrive at the quantum-mechanical formalism.
I have given you just a glimpse of the way I teach quantum mechanics. You are not in a position to judge on that basis. I certainly show the students how quantum physics is taught elsewhere. There you are confronted with a set of axioms like the following:I don't think you have made any _clearer_ quantum mechanics. I think that an introduction to quantum theory should NOT talk about these issues, and should limit itself to a statement that there ARE issues, but that these issues can only reasonably discussed once one understands the formalism. I think that anyone FORCING upon the novice a particular view is not doing any service to the novice.
You know well enough that the contextuality of the more general situations I mentioned rules out such a probability distribution. In Bohmian mechanics every observable except position is contextual. The relevant Einstein quote here is: "Everything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler."the simplest set of laws, to me, would be an overall probability distribution (hidden variable approach). THAT is intuitively understandable, this is what Einstein taught should be done, and this is, for instance, what Bohmians insist upon. This is the simplest, and most intuitive approach to the introduction of "ordinary" objects, no ?
If Alice and Bob perceive a teapot on the table between them, it is useful to assume that the reason this is so is that there is a teapot on the table between them. I agree. But quantum mechanics has many experimentally confirmed consequences that are totally inconsistent with the conception of a world of self-existent objects with self-existent properties (which could then be considered as the causes of our perceptions). Moreover, it has nothing to do with perceptions. It has everything to do with measuring devices (recall my definition) and their relation to the rest of the world.I wanted to indicate that if you have postulated an ontological concept from which you DERIVE observations, that this is more helpful than to stick to the observations themselves, and that such an ontology makes certain aspects, such as the relationship between different kinds of observations, more obvious.
I am not concerned with classical contexts. I want to understand the quantum world.in a classical context, your approach of claiming that we should only look at an algorithm that relates outcomes of measurement, and not think of anything ontological behind it, is counter productive.
Of course not in classical physics. But the classical world is a fiction. I want to understand the real world which is quantum. (Sounds familiar, eh?)You have difficulties imagining there is an Euclidean space in classical physics ?
What I'm saying is that if you want to describe the unmeasured quantum world, the only way to do it is in terms of the probabilities of the possible outcomes of unperformed measurements. How do you describe, say, a hydrogen atom in a stationary state? This stationary state is a probability algorithm, which is based on the outcomes of three measurements: energy, total angular momentum, and one angular momentum component. It assigns probabilities to the possible outcomes of every possible measurement. Now if you want this algorithm to be a description of the hydrogen atom, then it’s a description in terms of the possible outcomes of unperformed measurements, right? And what is the salient feature of the atom thus described? Unschärfe or fuzziness!But you seemed to imply that there was also a kind of "existence" to POTENTIAL outcomes of measurement in the quantum case: it was a "fuzzy" variable, but as I understood, it DID exist, somehow. I had the impression you said that there WAS a position, even unmeasured, but that it was not a real number, but a "fuzzy variable".
That's why I won't be able even to make you see (let alone accept) my point of view. As said, to me it simply makes no sense to think of a probability algorithm as something that REALLY exists, and if the wave function is not really a probability algorithm, I haven’t the faintest notion what it could be, nor can you tell me.I take on the position that… there REALLY is a wave function.
No, it's the idea that a probability algorithm REALLY exists, or the fact that you can't tell me what the wave function is if it's not a probability algorithm.It is the idea that "your measurement apparatus can be in a superposition but you only see one term of it"
??!?So you have one "branch" or "world" or whatever, where you observe that D1 clicked and D2 didn't, and you have another one where D1 didn't click and D2 did…. No bafflement.
Good Lord!Well, Einstein's elements of reality are simply the wavefunction,
Not to me.and everything becomes clear, no ?
You are right to call it a dogma, as in religion.To me, the fundamental dogma of physics is the assumption that all of nature IS a mathematical structure (or, if you want to, that maps perfectly on a mathematical structure). Up to us to discover that structure. It's a Platonic view of things.
Sorry. According to you, Maxwell's equations allow us to calculate the effects of charges on the electromagnetic field (as well as the effect of the electromagnetic field on itself), and the Lorentz force law allows us to calculate the effects of the electromagnetic field on charges. According to me, who has never seen an electromagnetic field but only interacting charges, the electromagnetic field is a tool for calculating the action of charges on charges. I'm not quite on my own here.I don't follow what you're talking about ? We have no tool for calculating the interactions between charges and the EM field ?
Maybe I should explain this in a new thread. Maybe I will!vanesch said:I don't see how you are constructing a conception of the quantum world which is strongly objective, if you START by saying that we only have an algorithm, and no description!
Not by pure reasoning alone. I assume that those "ordinary" objects (which "occupy" space and neither collapse nor explode the moment they are created) are composed of a (large but) finite number of objects that do not "occupy" space, either because they are pointlike or because they have no form at all. Like many physicists these days, particularly quantum field theorist, quantum theory in general and the standard model in particular are here to stay as effective theories. In this sense Wilczek (Nobel 2004) refers to the standard model simply as "the theory of matter" (Wilczek, "Future summary", International Journal of Modern Physics A 16, 1653-78, 2001).Well, you consider quantum theory then solidly PROVEN beyond doubt, and by pure reasoning ?? And what if one day, quantum theory is falsified ? Do familiar objects disappear in a puff of logic then ?
Not the ONE AND ONLY POSSIBLE PHYSICAL THEORY that makes logical sense, but an effective theory that will survive whatever underlying theory might one day be unearthed. (My own intuition tells me that all there is is effective theories. The ultimate mathematical theory is a myth invented by the Pythagoreans.)So you seem to claim that, from the pure observation of the existence of ordinary objects, the ONE AND ONLY POSSIBLE PHYSICAL THEORY that makes logical sense is quantum theory ? No need for any empirical input then ? If only we would have been thinking harder, it would have been OBVIOUS that quantum theory is the ultimate correct theory ?
My bet is that not only quantum theory but the entire Pythagorean mind set, which thinks of reality in terms of mathematical structures, will be dead and gone. (Which is one of the reason why I'm looking beyond the quantum formalism for the relation between it and a non-mathematical reality.I'd bet that… 500 or 1000 years from now, quantum theory is an old and forgotten theory (except maybe for simplified calculations, as is classical physics today).
The mathematical formalism stands. The claptrap about evolving real wave functions won't survive.Quantum theory being the current paradigm, it is only waiting to be falsified, no ?
Wish it would. The quantum formalism has come of age. Its ontology is as yet nowhere in sight, thanks to the Pythagorean bias of most physicists.But that doesn't mean that in the mean time, we should not build up an ontological picture of what we have, now, today, in order to make sense of it. With a formalism comes an ontology.
But this is exactly what I'm saying. Quantum physics, taken seriously as a probability algorithm, implies a spacetime ontology that is inconsistent with that of classical physics. Yet this classical spacetime ontology is taken for granted by virtually every physicist. This is another reason why we find it so hard to beat sense into quantum mechanics.But trying to force upon a certain formalism, the ontology of another one, and you have troubles. Trying to force upon quantum theory, the ontology of classical physics, and you create a whole lot of pseudoproblems.
koantum said:No, there isn’t. Even vanesch agreed with that https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=948676&postcount=16".
koantum said:If I talk to quantum-state realists, they think I belong to the shut-up-and-calculate (SUC) sect. If I talk to members of this sect, they take me for a quantum-state realist. As far as I am concerned, they are both wrong.
The quantum-state realists aspire to describe the objective features of the quantum world. So do I. But they insist on describing these features without reference to measurements, and this doesn’t work.
Next you are told that this is the way it is. Admittedly, there are problems with this set of axioms, but you won't be able to understand them. So for now, shut up and calculate. If you want to know, for example, why energy is a Hermitean operator, you have to figure it out for yourself. You are not even told that the concept of energy in quantum mechanics is totally different from the corresponding classical concept.
If those poor students were told that the quantum formalism is nothing but an algorithm for assigning probabilities to possible measurement outcomes on the basis of actual outcomes, all of the above axioms would at once make sense to them.
The difference between the quantal and the classical probability algorithm is readily understood as a consequence of Nature's fuzziness, and the latter is readily understood as Nature's means to "fluff out" matter: to create stable objects that occupy space out of finite numbers of particles that don’t.
If Alice and Bob perceive a teapot on the table between them, it is useful to assume that the reason this is so is that there is a teapot on the table between them. I agree. But quantum mechanics has many experimentally confirmed consequences that are totally inconsistent with the conception of a world of self-existent objects with self-existent properties (which could then be considered as the causes of our perceptions). Moreover, it has nothing to do with perceptions. It has everything to do with measuring devices (recall my definition) and their relation to the rest of the world.
Of course not in classical physics. But the classical world is a fiction. I want to understand the real world which is quantum. (Sounds familiar, eh?)
What I'm saying is that if you want to describe the unmeasured quantum world, the only way to do it is in terms of the probabilities of the possible outcomes of unperformed measurements.
How do you describe, say, a hydrogen atom in a stationary state? This stationary state is a probability algorithm, which is based on the outcomes of three measurements: energy, total angular momentum, and one angular momentum component. It assigns probabilities to the possible outcomes of every possible measurement. Now if you want this algorithm to be a description of the hydrogen atom, then it’s a description in terms of the possible outcomes of unperformed measurements, right? And what is the salient feature of the atom thus described? Unschärfe or fuzziness!
That's why I won't be able even to make you see (let alone accept) my point of view. As said, to me it simply makes no sense to think of a probability algorithm as something that REALLY exists, and if the wave function is not really a probability algorithm, I haven’t the faintest notion what it could be, nor can you tell me.
You are right to call it a dogma, as in religion.
Sorry. According to you, Maxwell's equations allow us to calculate the effects of charges on the electromagnetic field (as well as the effect of the electromagnetic field on itself), and the Lorentz force law allows us to calculate the effects of the electromagnetic field on charges. According to me, who has never seen an electromagnetic field but only interacting charges, the electromagnetic field is a tool for calculating the action of charges on charges. I'm not quite on my own here.
The electromagnetic field is, after all, a mental construct introduced for the purpose of discussing interactions between charges. (E.H. Wichmann, Berkeley Physics Course Vol. 4, 1967; original emphasis.)
If a theory mistakes possibilities for actualities I don’t say it works. I say it's a silly category mistake.vanesch said:MWI works.
You would tell your students that energy doesn’t mean anything?The hamiltonian is the generator of the postulated unitary time translation one-parameter group. We call it "energy" but that doesn't mean anything. We could have called it "smurkadosh".
The word "algorithm" was used centuries before Turing.I prefer "formalism" and not "algorithm" because it is not directly runnable on a Turing machine.
Rather, we first define our concepts and then we see how we measure them. Energy, for instance, is the quantity whose conservation is implied by the homogeneity of time. For position it's of course obvious how we define and measure it."given an apparatus, what measurement operator goes with it and why ?"
I fully agree. Unfortunately the fact that we use this formalism to calculate the probabilities of measurement outcomes is usually mentioned almost as an afterthought. I'd be very happy if the first thing students are told is that the quantum formalism is a probability algorithm.What we are discussing about, however, is: can we assign some REALITY to this formalism ? Does the formalism indicate us an ontology ? And *this* metaphysical question should not be directly addressed: I think that it is good to say that you should first understand the formalism, as a way to calculate outcomes of measurements.
Asking what the laws of physics must be like if they are to allow the existence of "ordinary" objects (as defined by me) is one thing. Asking what Nature has in mind is quite another."nature's fuzziness that is meant to stabilize ordinary objects taking up a finite amount of space". Come on ! Nature has no "aim to produce stabilized ordinary objects" does it ?
Really? You can take a wave function and derive sensory perceptions from it? Wishful thinking! Neuroscientists can't even derive sensations from the neurobiology.the state of the wave function, from which the perceptions can be DERIVED (contextually).
Where did I ever say this? I insist that no property or value is possessed (by a system or an observable) unless the possession is indicated by a measurement!This is clinging too much onto naive realism, in that "measurement-observation-perception = reality". It is the basic tenet of the classical world view: the state of a system is given by what I could possibly measure of it: all potential measurement outcomes "are" there.
A measurement outcome is the indicated outcome of a system apparatus interaction. I cannot imagine anything else.You cannot imagine, apparently, that a "measurement result" is just the perceived outcome of an interaction
What IS the ontology of quantum theory? You are stating a tautology. What you are saying is as plausible as a baker's claim that the ONLY thing that you can use to describe an ontology is dough.The wave function is a mathematical object that maps upon the ontology of quantum theory, and to me, the ONLY thing that you can use to describe an ontology, is a mathematical object.
Lack of imagination, I'd say.But I wonder, what ELSE but a mathematical object could possibly satisfy "a description of an ontology" ?
Careful with that. Light (electromagnetic radiation) is instrumental in my seeing things. I don’t see the light by which I see. If I saw all that electromagnetic radiation that according to the classical story is crisscrossing the space between me and the objects I perceive, I couldn’t perceive these objects.In fact, you've never SEEN anything ELSE but some electromagnetic radiation (which is called "light in your eyes").
Comb your hair in dry air in front of a mirror and you'll see a charged object – yourself.I've, for my part, never SEEN a charge
No you haven’t, not directly. What you've see is material things from which you infer (rightly or wrongly) the presence of field modes.field modes ... Some of which I've seen directly.
koantum said:If a theory mistakes possibilities for actualities I don’t say it works.
If someone says the wave function is a probability algorithm on weekdays and Ultimate Reality on Sundays, I say: make up your mind.
Some MWI enthusiasts (Vaidman and Plaga come to mind) have claimed that it is an in principle testable interpretation. Imagine a test for the validity of MWI. There will then be worlds in which it is true as well as worlds in which it is false. Something for everyone.![]()
You would tell your students that energy doesn’t mean anything?
The word "algorithm" was used centuries before Turing.
Rather, we first define our concepts and then we see how we measure them. Energy, for instance, is the quantity whose conservation is implied by the homogeneity of time. For position it's of course obvious how we define and measure it.
I fully agree. Unfortunately the fact that we use this formalism to calculate the probabilities of measurement outcomes is usually mentioned almost as an afterthought. I'd be very happy if the first thing students are told is that the quantum formalism is a probability algorithm.
koantum said:Perhaps I should tell you something about our students at the Sri Aurobindo International Centre of Education and my class. In the so-called "free-progress" section of our higher secondary and undergraduate levels, students are free to choose their subjects and their teachers (from a list of available teachers and subjects offered, of course). Everyone of my students has chosen to be in my class, which is offered (i) to physics students as a philosophical complement to their regular physics classes and (ii) to students more interested in philosophy than science per se.
Asking what the laws of physics must be like if they are to allow the existence of "ordinary" objects (as defined by me) is one thing. Asking what Nature has in mind is quite another.
It would make more sense to take sense perceptions as your starting point and then discover the correlations between sensory data we call measurement outcomes. This way you don’t have to (and of course can't) derive perceptions because the quantum formalism is embedded in and presupposes sensory perceptions.
My approach differs from this in that it makes not sensory perceptions but measurements primary. Recall: any event or state of affairs from which the truth or the falsity of a statement about something can be inferred qualifies as a measurement outcome.
You want to derive from the wave function the existence of events or states of affairs from which something can be inferred? IMO this is as impossible as explaining why there is anything rather than nothing at all.
What you do is to transmogrify the correlations among perceptions into What Exists, after which you are left with the pseudo-problem of deriving the perceptions from What Exists.
A measurement outcome is the indicated outcome of a system apparatus interaction. I cannot imagine anything else.
Careful with that. Light (electromagnetic radiation) is instrumental in my seeing things. I don’t see the light by which I see. If I saw all that electromagnetic radiation that according to the classical story is crisscrossing the space between me and the objects I perceive, I couldn’t perceive these objects.
Comb your hair in dry air in front of a mirror and you'll see a charged object – yourself.
No you haven’t, not directly. What you've see is material things from which you infer (rightly or wrongly) the presence of field modes.
We went through this: you then need some extra postulate to get the only things (probabilities) that you can compare with experiments.They only say that it is ultimate reality ; they don't say it is a probability algorithm.
It could of course be the other way: there are NO universes in which the outcome is true.Unless the test is "sure" (100% probability), in which case, there are NO universes in which the outcome is false.
I almost agree. Energy means a lot of things in the limit in which quantum mechanics degenerates into classical mechanics, and it's worth discussing (I'm not proposing to do that here!) how and why these classical significances arise from the defining property.Energy doesn't mean anything BEYOND its defining property, which is the generator of time translations. For instance, the fact that "energy is conserved" is ONLY the result of the fact that it is the generator of time translations. And energy doesn't have much other uses except for the fact that it is a conserved quantity over time.
What? Before it didn’t have a mathematical meaning? But OK. What if I say that quantum states are "probability measures" instead of "probability algorithms". Is this more acceptable? A measure on the set of projectors? I'm afraid this term sounds too Boolean.Yes, but Turing gave it its mathematical definition.
I am with you most of the way. But this is another topic that is best treated separately. I'll get back to it.No, it isn't. That's the whole point I wanted to outline. The "obvious" comes simply from "habits, what they told you, how people used to do it...", and from the fact that we have rather good visual impressions which give us an impression of "seeing positions". How do you determine, say, the width of 10^(-23) m ? Or of 10^17 m ? "position" is simply a "common sense" (probably biologically evolved) mental concept, not more than "light or dark" or something of the kind.
Perhaps it was different in my time (the 70s) and my country (then Germany). People talked and wrote as if state vectors or wave functions represented systems somehow directly, not merely as tools for calculating the probabilities of measurement outcomes.Funny, but that's what they told me, and how I understood most intro texts to the matter.
Please allow for the fact that we touched on only a small part of the philosophy so far.vanesch said:Well, there's not much philosophy in your approach, I'd say.
I purposely didn’t commit myself as to the ontological status of fuzzy observables. All I said is: if you want to describe a quantum system between measurements, the only way to do this is in terms of assignments of probabilities to the possible outcomes of unperformed measurements. All right, I characterized the resulting probability distributions as descriptive of an objective fuzziness in order to distinguish it from a merely subjective ignorance. Our ignorance of the electron's position doesn’t stabilize the hydrogen atom. Its objective fuzziness does.I even fail to see EXACTLY what your approach is about, except to vaguely say that one should NOT assign any reality to the wave function, but to the "fuzziness" of potential measurement outcomes.
You assume too much about yourself as creator of your world. You won't find your way in Paris using a map of London. There is a correspondence in the sense that Nature will knock you on the nose if you use the wrong theory. In this sense there is a correct theory.we're almost automatically organizing our subjective experiences in such a way to make the ontological hypothesis of the existence of "ordinary objects". You could call this a pre-build in "scientific theory" from which our brains "boot up". The internal perceptions make us also make the hypothesis that we have a physical body, included in the list of "ordinary objects".
OK so far but, as said, there is agreement (up to a point) between these organizing principles and whatever they are working on. The assumption of a self-existent world with self-existent objects with self-existent properties works so well that it may well be MEANT to work that well. If you can hold on to that for a microsecond, then we can understand the quantum formalism very well as the necessary mechanism by which what is MEANT to be is manifested, brought into being, or realized. Enough ontology for the day?But now, our physical theories may become more sophisticated, in such a way that they conflict with the "build in" common sense ontological hypotheses (the "existence of ordinary objects"). So one has then to make a choice, at least when one WANTS to make a hypothesis of ontology: should we stick to our "common sense" build in ontological hypotheses, or should we consider that these are what they are, namely just organizing principles of our daily subjective experiences
Not the ENTIRE. There are about as many solutions to the problem of interpretation as there are ways of formulating the problem. We've already noticed that the way one formulates the problem half predetermines the solution, and if the formulation produces a pseudo-problem, the solution is gratuitous.The ENTIRE interpretational difficulty of quantum theory resides in the refusal to let go our primary common sense ontological hypotheses ; the refusal to let go the idea that "ordinary objects are real".
You shouldn’t stop here. Only pre-linguistic experience can be trusted. The moment it is formulated, it is enmeshed in a system of questionable hypotheses.There is no absolute way to infer the truth or falsity of something, apart from the truth or falsity of a subjective experience.
Apparently there is a mirror symmetry between what I say about your approach and what you say about mine.you are MAKING IN ANY CASE ontological assumptions. If, by doing so, you introduce problems, then that's of course more a problem of the assumptions than of the theory at hand.
Nonsense. There are plenty more choices. You are limited to these choices only because you confuse mathematics with ontology.Ha, but that [to transmogrify the correlations among perceptions into What Exists] is EXACTLY the nature of the hypothesis of an ontology! You have the choice between that, and solipsism.
This just means we have different ideas about what a quantum-mechanical way is.Me: A measurement outcome is the indicated outcome of a system apparatus interaction.
You: But there is no quantum-mechanical way to do that!
Sorry, I know exactly the opposite (to the extent that you allow me to know anything).You know as well as I that if you track down the physical interaction of the system and the apparatus, that both end up in an entangled state, not in a "definite outcome" state.
Sorry, haven’t seen light entering my eyes. Only see things with the help of the light entering my eyes.You only see the light that enters your eyes, no ?
The bottom line: everyone sees what they want to see.I'll "see" an EM field penetrating my eyes, which has such a structure that it makes, according my build-in common sense ontological hypotheses, me postulate that there is an object in front of me, called mirror, and that this mirror projects light upon me that must come from what's in front of the mirror, namely my body.
What? Before it didn’t have a mathematical meaning? But OK. What if I say that quantum states are "probability measures" instead of "probability algorithms". Is this more acceptable? A measure on the set of projectors? I'm afraid this term sounds too Boolean.
Perhaps it was different in my time (the 70s) and my country (then Germany). People talked and wrote as if state vectors or wave functions represented systems somehow directly, not merely as tools for calculating the probabilities of measurement outcomes.
And even when the relation between wave functions and probabilities was discussed, it was biased and unbalanced. The fact that wave functions determine probabilities of measurement outcomes was emphasized, whereas the fact that measurement outcomes determine wave functions was blunted by an embarrassed "it seems so".
koantum said:Not the ENTIRE. There are about as many solutions to the problem of interpretation as there are ways of formulating the problem. We've already noticed that the way one formulates the problem half predetermines the solution, and if the formulation produces a pseudo-problem, the solution is gratuitous.
I see no reason to let go the idea that ordinary objects are real. There is much more to them than commonsense has it but that doesn’t make them unreal.
The problem is to understand the relation between the quantum formalism and ordinary objects. That you need the quantum formalism in order to have them is just one of them. Another is that the quantum formalism describes how ordinary objects are manifested, brought into being, made to exist, whatever. I mentioned elsewhere that it should be expected that the microworld doesn’t have the same features as the macroworld, for if it did, one could never understand how these features are realized, brought into being….
I fully agree with you.vanesch said:I jump up and down, each time I read that one CANNOT GIVE an ontological description to the quantum-mechanical formalism without running severely in contradictions, because this is not true.
You will get into trouble if you take wave functions for real, for then a cat can be both alive and dead, which is pure nonsense. You won't arrive at this nonsense of you understand that the quantum formalism does nothing but correlate measurement outcomes, whose existence it presupposes. To make your approach consistent with the existence of measurement outcomes, you need many worlds. I want to understand this one world. The plural of "world" is (for me) a contradiction in terms.it is pretty obvious that you will arrive at troubles when you take ordinary objects for real: that is the very superposition principle of quantum theory, which cannot be applied to ordinary objects, if they are to be real.
How about Pythagorean mysticism?Call it reductionism, or platonic realism or whatever.
Absolutely not. I haven’t yet told you what my fundamental ontological entities are. To be able to conceive of them, you need to accept the quantum formalism as being fundamentally a probability algorithm.Yours is that the ordinary objects you see are the "fundamental ontological entities" in some sort of way.
Apropos of Kolmogorov. There are two misconceptions about quantum-mechanical probabilities:Well, you know that strictly speaking, quantum states are NOT probability measures over the potential measurement outcomes, at least not in the Kolmogorov sense
Wrong. There is a crucial difference between macroscopic objects and all the rest. But (once again) to be able to understand it, you need to accept the quantum formalism as being fundamentally a probability algorithm.After all, there's no distinction between a quantum system under study and your body, right ?
There happens to be a world. Why? You tell me?You happen to perceive *A* precise outcome, not a fuzzy one. Why ? You tell me.