reenmachine said:
OK but if there would be something else than A and M , like for example (F,A,M,P) , would it be called a quadruple?
Yes, I think "quadruple" would be appropriate. You can also call it a "4-tuple". The term for an ordered set ##(x_1,\dots,x_n)## with n members is "ordered n-tuple". But I think the it's kind of superfluous to include the word "ordered", since people who say "n-tuple" always mean "ordered n-tuple".
reenmachine said:
This is where self-teaching mathematics gets tricky.''Studying the basics of set theory'' might not be that hard , but knowing where to find the right stuff in the right order is where it gets complicated.I will follow your advice and try to understand the concepts of function and cartesian product.
I don't think you will need to read a book on set theory just yet. What you need is a brief summary of the main ideas that's no more than ten pages long. Unfortunately I don't know a good place to find such a summary.
In addition to functions and cartesian products, you will also need to understand subsets, unions, intersections, complements, differences and Venn diagrams. You also need to understand the symbols ##\forall## ("for all"), ##\exists## ("there exists"), ##\in## ("is a member of").
I'll explain a few things here. A set can be thought of as a collection of objects. There are two ways to specify a set. The first is to explicitly list its members. For example, the set whose members are 1, 2 and 3 is denoted by {1,2,3}. The second is to specify another set and a property that some of its members has. For example, let ##\mathbb Z## be the set of all integers. The set of all odd integers can be written as ##\{n\in\mathbb Z|n\text{ is odd}\}##.
Two sets A and B are equal if and only if every member of A is a member of B and every member of B is a member of A. This means that {1,2,3}={3,1,2} and that {1,2,2,2,7}={7,7,2,1}={1,2,7}.
Ordered n-tuples are a lot like sets that are specified in the first of the two ways discussed above, but the condition for equality is different than the corresponding condition for sets. For example, the triples (a,b,c)=(d,e,f) are equal if and only if a=d, b=e and c=f. It's also impossible for an n-tuple to be equal to an m-tuple unless m=n.
reenmachine said:
I understand your philosophical argument about finding a level from which to stop asking why , but I find it pretty confusing that we wouldn't know what a set is or what a member of set is if we use them...
You'll get used to it.
Note that the alternative is to not know what a real number is, what an integer is, etc. In the context of set theory, these things can all be given exact definitions.
reenmachine said:
The domain is each member of a set , is the codomain also a domain if it's part of the set?
The domain is a set. The codomain of a function ##f:X\to Y## is also the domain of some function ##g:Y\to Z##. The domain and codomain of a function f is often the same set. Consider e.g. the function ##f:\mathbb R\to\mathbb R## defined by f(x)=x+3 for all x in ℝ. Its domain is the set of all real numbers, and so is its codomain.
reenmachine said:
In your example , X represents every member of the set and the function turns all the members of the set into Y
X is a set. You can say that f associates exactly one member of Y with each member of X, or that f "takes" members of X to members of Y. If f(x)=x+3 for all x in ℝ, then f takes 3 to 7, ##\pi## to ##\pi+3##, etc.
reenmachine said:
, which is only a part of the set , therefore all members of a set becomes like the co-domain?
I don't understand this part.
reenmachine said:
the A and B part of your paragraph sounds simple but I don't understand.What is a compared to A? Why is a part of A?
##a## is a member of A. (Another way to say that is ##a## is an element of ##A##). Why is it a member? Because I said so.

Let's look at what I said again. I said that ##A\times B## is defined as the set of all ##(a,b)## such that ##a\in A## and ##b\in B##. (##\in## means "is a member of"). In the fancy notation,
$$A\times B=\{(a,b)|a\in A,\, b\in B\}.$$ (This notation actually violates the rules I just mentioned about how to specify a set, because I'm not mentioning what set the pairs (a,b) belong to, but since I know that there
is such a set, it's safe to say that this abuse of notation won't cause any problems later). One of the most useful examples is the set
$$\mathbb R^2= \mathbb R\times\mathbb R =\{(x,y)|x,y\in\mathbb R\}.$$ The set ##R## can be interpreted as a line. The set ##\mathbb R^2## can be interpreted as a plane.
reenmachine said:
I'm still not sure what a set is suppose to be or what the purpose of having a set.I think I'm lacking context here.
Don't worry, you will encounter thousands of examples when you study math.
reenmachine said:
So basically both F doesn't mean the same thing? FxF are functions and F is the field , so in your previous ordered triple you had A & M , which would be A x M into F? (F,A,M)
No, F is a set, and F×F is a set. Specifically, it's the set of all ordered pairs (x,y) such that both x and y are members of F. A and M are the functions, both with domain F×F and codomain F. I indicated this by writing ##A:F\times F\to F## and ##M:F\times F\to F##. It's the triple (F,A,M) that may or may not be a field, depending on whether it satisfies the field axioms or not. If (F,A,M) is a field, the proper way to refer to F is as "the underlying set of the field (F,A,M)", but no one actually does that. It's standard to abuse the terminology by referring to F as a field if (F,A,M) is a field. Similarly, when people talk about members "of the field", they mean members of its underlying set F.
reenmachine said:
Another quick point about your last sentence , if A is addition we'll use + instead of A , so why the need to ever write A (x,y)?
I just thought the explanation would be clearer that way. Note that you don't know if A is the addition operation of a field until after you have checked if it satisfies the field axioms. So you don't know at the start if the + notation is appropriate.
reenmachine said:
Not sure I understand what you mean when you're saying ''there are terms that only satisfy some of the field axioms''.Do you mean like in the example you gave me about the x1 x2 etc...? How do you drop axioms for multiplication?
No, I meant like in the definition of "ring" that I included in my previous post. (I didn't say exactly what you put in quotes. I didn't mention "terms" that may or may not satisfy the field axioms. I mentioned that there are terms (i.e. words) reserved for triples (F,A,M) that only satisfy some of the axioms). A triple (F,A,M) is said to be a
field if it satisfies all 9 of the
field axioms. A triple (F,A,M) is said to be a
ring if it satisfies the first 7 of the field axioms. That's what I meant by "dropping" some of the axioms.
The set of integers is a good example of a ring. It has an addition operation and a multiplication operation that satisfy 8 of the field axioms. The axiom that isn't satisfied is the one that says that every member of the set except 0 has a multiplicative inverse. For example, 1/3 isn't an integer.
You probably shouldn't spend too much time on understanding abstract algebra right now. This is typical third-year stuff. But you
should study a few pages of set theory as soon as possible.