Timelike v. spacelike, is it arbitrary?

  • Thread starter Thread starter BruceW
  • Start date Start date
  • #51
ghwellsjr said:
Your supposition is speculation, isn't it? It has nothing to do with the universe we live in, the physics we use to describe it, or teaching relativity which is the purpose of this forum.
I was just saying that if we use the definition that all matter travels along timelike curves, then yes, we can say which curves are timelike and which are spacelike. But If we do not use this definition, then we cannot.

ghwellsjr said:
Your misunderstanding that Proper Time or a time-like spacetime intervals are no different than Proper Length or space-like spacetime intervals or null spacetime intervals is not part of teaching Special Relativity. You are attempting to promote something different.
I agree that we can choose a set of time-like curves and a set of space-like curves. But I am saying that for a given physical situation, it is our choice for which ones are time-like and which ones are space-like. (Unless we define all matter to travel along timelike curves, in which case the choice is made for us by this definition).
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
BruceW, besides the physical point which I am making there is the geometrical point which WBN and PD are making. The geometry is determined by the metric. Any Lorentzian metric will have three eigenvalues with one sign and one eigenvalue with the opposite sign. The eigenvector corresponding to the one with the opposite sign is timelike. No matter, no physics, pure relativity, pure geometry. The only way that you can make it ambiguous is by NOT specifying the geometry (i.e. by not specifying the metric).

Simply put, there is no way in which the choice is arbitrary. It is constrained by the geometry, it is constrained by the physics, that is as far from arbitrary as is possible. The only possible ambiguity/arbitraryness comes from not specifying either the geometry or the physics.
 
  • #53
BruceW said:
But now, suppose we come across some not-normal matter that moves along a space-like interval. Again, suppose it is like a muon, i.e. the amount of muons that decay depends only on the arc length that the beam has traveled. Now, we could use this weird matter to measure the arc length along a space-like interval, simply by observing the fraction of muons that remain, since this tells us the arc length along that path.

Have you actually tried to construct such a model? If so, please show your work, as I asked before. If not, you are just waving your hands and assuming that such a model would work the way you say and still be consistent. That's why I asked you before to actually do the math, instead of just speculating. (And you should really look into the literature on tachyon models; as I've said a couple of times already, there are subtleties lurking there.)
 
  • #54
PeterDonis said:
Have you actually tried to construct such a model? If so, please show your work, as I asked before. If not, you are just waving your hands and assuming that such a model would work the way you say and still be consistent. That's why I asked you before to actually do the math, instead of just speculating. (And you should really look into the literature on tachyon models; as I've said a couple of times already, there are subtleties lurking there.)
Isn't it still speculation, even if he does come up with consistent math?
 
  • #55
BruceW said:
OK, so let's say we have components a,b,c,d (and the order I have listed them does not imply anything about the metric). (And I have avoided the usual t,x,y,z because that would imply which component should be the timelike component). Now, let's say I look at a path that goes completely along the c component. Is this path timelike or spacelike?

There is no way to tell, because I have not told you which component is the timelike component.

No, there's no way to tell because you haven't told us what the metric is. Which means, as DaleSpam said, that you aren't doing physics; you're just throwing letters and numbers around. As soon as you define a metric, you have defined which paths are timelike and which are spacelike. You don't have to make any assumptions about what kinds of objects travel on what kinds of paths.
 
Last edited:
  • #56
ghwellsjr said:
Isn't it still speculation, even if he does come up with consistent math?

"Speculation" is a broad word. PF's prohibition is on "personal" speculation. There is, as I mentioned, plenty of literature on tachyon models, so talking about those models and what kinds of subtleties arise in them would not be personal speculation, even though no tachyons have ever actually been observed.
 
  • #57
BruceW said:
for a given physical situation, it is our choice for which ones are time-like and which ones are space-like.

Incorrect; the "physical situation" includes the metric, which, as I said, determines which curves are timelike and which are spacelike, regardless of what kinds of objects travel on what kinds of paths.
 
  • #58
BruceW said:
we both agree that when there is no matter around, such a model works fine, right?

No, I don't, because you haven't shown me such a model. I can't say anything about such a model until you actually show me one.
 
  • #59
I'm trying to think of different ways to explain the point I'm trying to get across... OK, suppose we have some model for the universe, and we have chosen a metric with signature (-1,1,1,1). OK, now instead let's say we choose the metric with signature (1,-1,1,1). Then is our new physical description going to work as well? (apart from the fact that matter only travels along timelike curves).

I would (intuitively) say that our new physical description would also work. As long as our equations are manifestly covariant, then I would be surprised that a (-1,1,1,1) metric would work but a (1,-1,1,1) metric would not. (again, ignoring the fact that matter travels along timelike curves).

edit: to be more specific, when I say "instead choose the metric with signature..." I mean keep things like the stress-energy tensor and the distribution of matter the same. But choose the metric to be different (i.e. choose a different timelike component).
 
  • #60
What you described is not a different signature; the number of ##+## and ##-## signs are the same in both.
 
Last edited:
  • #61
BruceW said:
I'm trying to think of different ways to explain the point I'm trying to get across... OK, suppose we have some model for the universe, and we have chosen a metric with signature (-1,1,1,1). OK, now instead let's say we choose the metric with signature (1,-1,1,1). Then is our new physical description going to work as well?

We don't know, because you haven't given us a physical description. You haven't given us an actual metric; you've just played around with which order you write the coordinates. Show us an actual metric--an actual expression for ##ds^2## in terms of your coordinates--and we'll be able to tell you which curves are timelike and which are spacelike. But if all you've written down is a 4-tuple of signs, you haven't written down any physics; you've just juggled coordinate labels, and they're not really labeling anything anyway since you haven't written down a metric.

BruceW said:
to be more specific, when I say "instead choose the metric with signature..." I mean keep things like the stress-energy tensor and the distribution of matter the same. But choose the metric to be different (i.e. choose a different timelike component).

This makes no sense. I really, really think you need to stop waving your hands and try doing this for a specific, explicit model, so you can see what's actually involved. You are relying way too much on your intuition without grounding your intuition in any actual physics. By a specific, explicit model I mean, once again, writing down an explicit expression for ##ds^2## in terms of some set of coordinates, as well as any other physical quantities you want--stress-energy tensor, whatever. Then try to "choose the metric to be different" in that specific case and see what happens.
 
  • #62
WannabeNewton said:
What you described is not a different signature; the number of ##+## and ##-## signs are the same in both.
That's good. I want it to still have the same number of plus and minus signs. Ah, I see. the term 'signature' just means the number of plus and minus signs. OK, sorry I was not using correct terminology. right, what I meant to say, is to keep the same signature, but change which component is the 'odd one out'.
 
  • #63
BruceW said:
what I meant to say, is to keep the same signature, but change which component is the 'odd one out'.

This has no meaning unless you write down an expression for ##ds^2##, as I keep on asking you to do. The ordering of the coordinates means nothing by itself.
 
  • #64
PeterDonis said:
We don't know, because you haven't given us a physical description. You haven't given us an actual metric; you've just played around with which order you write the coordinates. Show us an actual metric--an actual expression for ##ds^2## in terms of your coordinates--and we'll be able to tell you which curves are timelike and which are spacelike.
hmm. Now I think about it, any metric which is isotropic in 3 of its dimensions is forced to have the other dimension as the timelike dimension. But this argument doesn't work for a metric which is not isotropic. Alright, I concede a lot of ground here! :) If our metric is isotropic in 3 of its dimensions, then I agree that the timelike curves are automatically defined for us. But I still maintain that for a non-isotropic metric, we have an arbitrary choice of which dimension is the timelike one.
 
  • #65
as an example of a metric which is not isotropic in just 3 of its dimensions, we have the simple metric: ds^2 = -dt^2 + dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2
In this case, our choice of timelike dimension is arbitrary.
 
  • #66
BruceW said:
I still maintain that for a non-isotropic metric, we have an arbitrary choice of which dimension is the timelike one.

This is incorrect; isotropy has nothing to do with it. Perhaps the problem here is that you have a mistaken understanding of what "isotropy" means:

BruceW said:
as an example of a metric which is not isotropic in just 3 of its dimensions, we have the simple metric: ds^2 = -dt^2 + dx^2 + dy^2 + dz^2
In this case, our choice of timelike dimension is arbitrary.

This metric *is* isotropic; it's just standard Minkowski spacetime. I think you need to clarify what you think "isotropic" means.
 
  • #67
PeterDonis said:
This is incorrect; isotropy has nothing to do with it. Perhaps the problem here is that you have a mistaken understanding of what "isotropy" means:
No, isotropy in 3 of the dimensions (but not the other one) is the entire reason why we can tell which curves are the timelike ones. And thank you very much for helping me to realize this. I think it is quite an important point in general relativity that I will try to remember.
PeterDonis said:
This metric *is* isotropic; it's just standard Minkowski spacetime. I think you need to clarify what you think "isotropic" means.
ah, but this metric is isotropic in all four dimensions. Therefore it does not force us to choose a particular dimension to be the timelike one. And I think I know what isotropy means. In wiki's page on the FLRW metric: "The FLRW metric starts with the assumption of homogeneity and isotropy of space." As they say, it is isotropic in the 3 'space' dimensions but not in the 'time' dimension. And it is the very fact that it is isotropic in 3 of the dimensions that forces us to choose the other dimension as the timelike dimension.
 
  • #68
BruceW said:
I agree that once you have specified if the curve is inside or outside the light cone, then the timelike or spacelike character of that line is fixed. What I am saying is that to begin with, specifying the curve to lie inside or outside the light cone is an arbitrary choice that we can make.

(Sorry for jumping back into the thread...)

In (3+1)-dimensional Minkowski spacetime,
the set of curves with [everywhere-]spacelike-tangent-vectors includes closed-spacelike curves
whereas the set with [everywhere-]timelike-tangent-vectors has no closed-timelike curves.

To detach the physical ideas of "space" and "time" from the words used,
it might be helpful to call the timelike curves "curves of the first kind (associated with [with my signature convention] positive square-norm)"
and the spacelike curves "curves of the second kind (associated with negative square-norm)".
 
  • #69
BruceW said:
No, isotropy in 3 of the dimensions (but not the other one)

I think I see what you are saying here, but your terminology is highly nonstandard. See below.

BruceW said:
this metric is isotropic in all four dimensions. Therefore it does not force us to choose a particular dimension to be the timelike one. And I think I know what isotropy means. In wiki's page on the FLRW metric: "The FLRW metric starts with the assumption of homogeneity and isotropy of space." As they say, it is isotropic in the 3 'space' dimensions but not in the 'time' dimension. And it is the very fact that it is isotropic in 3 of the dimensions that forces us to choose the other dimension as the timelike dimension.

Ok, here's how to state what you just stated here in standard terminology:

Minkowski spacetime and FLRW spacetime are both isotropic, because "isotropy" in the standard usage means "isotropy in the 3 spatial dimensions" in your usage.

Minkowski spacetime and FLRW spacetime are also both homogeneous; I think your usage of that word is the same as the standard usage.

Minkowski spacetime is stationary, because it has a timelike Killing vector field. What that means is that we can find timelike curves in Minkowski spacetime along which the metric remains unchanged. I think that stationary + isotropic in the standard usage is what corresponds to "isotropic in all 4 dimensions" in your usage.

FLRW spacetime is *not* stationary: there is no family of timelike curves along which the metric remains unchanged. So non-stationary + isotropic in the standard usage would correspond to "isotropic in the 3 spatial dimensions, but not in the time dimension" in your usage.

Having said all that: you still have not shown how we can arbitrarily choose the timelike direction in Minkowski spacetime. A spacetime being stationary does not allow you to do that. If you think it does, then please show how, explicitly. Don't just wave your hands and say you think it can be done. Show how it can be done.
 
  • #70
PeterDonis said:
Show how it can be done.

Perhaps it will help if I give an example that doesn't involve the timelike/spacelike distinction, to make it clearer why I and others are reacting so strongly to the idea that choosing the timelike direction is arbitrary.

Consider three points on the Earth's surface: the North Pole; Quito, Ecuador; and Nairobi, Kenya. Both of the cities are (to a good enough approximation for here) on the Earth's equator, and Nairobi is due East of Kenya, whereas the North Pole is due North of both.

Now consider a claim analogous to the one you (BruceW) have been making: the choice of which direction is "North" is arbitrary. I can just as easily set up coordinates in which Nairobi is due North of Quito.

Of course I can choose labels for the directions in any way I want; but all that does is change the meanings of the labels. If I pick labels for the directions such that Nairobi is due North of Quito, then what had been called the North Pole is now the West Pole, and is due West of both Quito and Nairobi. No actual geometry has changed; no actual physics has changed. I've just changed labels.

I could even make a more drastic coordinate change: I could pick coordinates such that Nairobi is due East of both Quito and the "North" Pole. But "North" in the name of the Pole now has to be in quotes because it's only North of Quito; it's not North of Nairobi in these new coordinates. Here I have not only changed labels, I've changed the orientation of the coordinate grid on the Earth (basically I've exchanged latitude and longitude).

But there is no arbitrary choice, of coordinates or anything else, I can make that will change the distance from Quito to Nairobi, or the distance between either of them and the North Pole, or the angles of the triangle formed by those three points (here "triangle" really means the figure on the Earth's surface formed by the three great circles connecting the pairs of points). There is also no arbitrary choice I can make that will change the fact that the "North Pole" (however it's labeled in my chosen coordinates) is on the Earth's axis of rotation, and Quito and Ecuador are both in a plane perpendicular to that axis. In that sense, the choice of "North" is *not* arbitrary; if by "North" I mean "the direction pointing at a place on the Earth's surface which is on its axis of rotation", then I can't arbitrarily choose which direction that is.

In the case of spacetime, what I and others have been saying is that your claim that you can arbitrarily choose the timelike direction is *not* like the claim that you can arbitrarily choose coordinates on the Earth, as above; it's like the claim that you can arbitrarily choose whether the North Pole or some other point is on the Earth's axis of rotation, or whether Quito and Nairobi, or some other points, are in the plane perpendicular to that axis. That's why we're so skeptical of your claim.
 
Last edited:
  • #71
PeterDonis said:
In that sense, the choice of "North" is *not* arbitrary; if by "North" I mean "the direction pointing at a place on the Earth's surface which is on its axis of rotation", then I can't arbitrarily choose which direction that is.

This also helps clarify, by the way, why the "isotropy" question is not relevant. "Isotropy" in the analogy I drew corresponds to the fact that there are *two* directions, at any point on the Earth's surface, that point towards where the Earth's rotation axis intersects the surface: North and South. I can indeed make an arbitrary choice of which one I label "North" and which one I label "South"; the physics doesn't pick out either one as "preferred". But that arbitrary choice doesn't change the fact that only two particular points on the Earth's surface, the two Poles, are on the Earth's axis; I can't change which points they are by making an arbitrary choice.

Similarly, in a stationary spacetime like Minkowski spacetime, the choice of which timelike direction to label "future" and which timelike direction to label "past" is arbitrary. The spacetime geometry itself doesn't pick out either direction as preferred (unlike the FLRW case, where the two timelike directions *are* different, because the change in the scale factor picks out one direction as "expanding" and the other as "contracting"). But that doesn't mean I can arbitrarily choose which dimension is timelike, any more than I can arbitrarily choose where the Earth's axis of rotation is.
 
  • #72
Isotropy is irrelevant, as are the coordinates used to represent the metric. A Lorentzian metric will have 4 eigenvalues, three will have one sign and one will have the other sign. The eigenvector corresponding to the other sign is timelike. Eigenvectors are independent of coordinates.
 
  • #73
PeterDonis said:
"isotropy" in the standard usage means "isotropy in the 3 spatial dimensions" in your usage.

Perhaps it's also worth expanding a bit on why this is standard usage. It's because "rotation" in a plane that includes the timelike dimension works differently than rotation in a plane that only includes spacelike dimensions. Invariance under the latter type of rotation is what motivates the term "isotropy".

Briefly, rotation in a plane that includes a timelike dimension (say the t-x plane in ordinary Minkowski coordinates) induces extra phenomena like time dilation and length contraction; rotation in a purely spacelike plane (say the x-y plane in ordinary Minkowski coordinates) does not. This gives another way to pick out the timelike dimension: you can induce a boost (a rotation that includes the timelike dimension and includes the extra phenomena mentioned above) in any of three orthogonal directions, meaning that there are three mutually orthogonal planes in spacetime that include the timelike dimension. The three mutually orthogonal directions in which the boost can be induced pick out the three spacelike dimensions; the fourth one, common to all three boost planes in spacetime, is the timelike dimension.
 
  • #74
PeterDonis said:
Minkowski spacetime is stationary, because it has a timelike Killing vector field. What that means is that we can find timelike curves in Minkowski spacetime along which the metric remains unchanged. I think that stationary + isotropic in the standard usage is what corresponds to "isotropic in all 4 dimensions" in your usage.

FLRW spacetime is *not* stationary: there is no family of timelike curves along which the metric remains unchanged. So non-stationary + isotropic in the standard usage would correspond to "isotropic in the 3 spatial dimensions, but not in the time dimension" in your usage.
ah right, sorry for using incorrect terminology again. thanks for explaining the proper way to say it. I'll remember that for next time.
 
  • #75
PeterDonis said:
But there is no arbitrary choice, of coordinates or anything else, I can make that will change the distance from Quito to Nairobi, or the distance between either of them and the North Pole...
true. Maybe this is a good way to 'mathematically' explain what I mean. yes, in relativity, our symmetry operations preserve the norm of vectors. But I don't see how this is justified. How about if I add another symmetry operation that does not preserve the norm of vectors? for example if we denote vectors by (V0,V1,V2,V3) then the operation of swapping V1 with V0 (for all vectors). But, we leave the metric as it was. clearly this does not preserve the norm. But doesn't it result in the same system? (Apart from the fact that some spacelike vectors will now become timelike vectors).

As said earlier, if our metric is isotropic, then doing the V1,V0 swap will change the system. for example, the vector might be the 4-momentum of matter in an FLRW universe. Once we do the swap, our system is no longer isotropic. But what about for a general metric that is not isotropic? (or, is isotropic, but also stationary?)
 
  • #76
as an example, for the Minkowski spacetime. Suppose we have metric (-1,1,1,1) and I am traveling along vector (1,0,0,0) and you are traveling along vector (0,1,0,0). So we would say I am traveling along a timelike curve and you are traveling along a spacelike curve. Now if we do the V1,V0 swap, I am now traveling along vector (0,1,0,0) and you are traveling along vector (1,0,0,0). So we would now say that I am traveling along a spacelike curve and you are traveling along a timelike curve.

These two systems are the same, so in this particular case, the V1,V0 swap is a symmetry operation of the system. It is not a symmetry operation of the Poincare group, but it is a symmetry operation of the system (which is the important thing in the first place). I know the issue here is that this is just a particular example. So it doesn't prove anything about other systems.
 
  • #77
BruceW said:
As said earlier, if our metric is isotropic, then doing the V1,V0 swap will change the system. for example, the vector might be the 4-momentum of matter in an FLRW universe. Once we do the swap, our system is no longer isotropic. But what about for a general metric that is not isotropic? (or, is isotropic, but also stationary?)
even in this case, maybe the system remains the same after the swap. Before the swap, all the matter was moving in the V0 direction, and the motion in the other directions was zero. Then after the swap, all the matter is moving in the V1 direction and the motion in the other directions is zero. So now, the system is 'isotropic' in the 3 directions V0,V2,V3. (and sorry, I know that the correct terminology for isotropic means a symmetry specifically in the directions V1,V2,V3. But I hope you'll excuse this abuse of notation, since I have explained what I mean by it).

So again, the only meaning I can see for the assignment of 'timelike' curves is that matter is defined to move along the timelike curves. (and if we forced this definition, then the above 'symmetry operation' would not be allowed).
 
  • #78
BruceW said:
These two systems are the same, so in this particular case, the V1,V0 swap is a symmetry operation of the system.
No, it isn't. In one case I can send signals to you but not vice versa, and in the other you can send signals to me but not vice versa. This is an easily distinguishable asymmetry.
 
  • #79
BruceW said:
So again, the only meaning I can see for the assignment of 'timelike' curves is that matter is defined to move along the timelike curves.
I don't know why you keep making this absurd statement when we have already discussed the fact that radiation defines the timelike direction too. Radiation and the metric identify timelike curves every bit as well as matter.
 
Last edited:
  • #80
BruceW said:
How about if I add another symmetry operation that does not preserve the norm of vectors? for example if we denote vectors by (V0,V1,V2,V3) then the operation of swapping V1 with V0 (for all vectors). But, we leave the metric as it was.

This is a logical contradiction. The metric determines the norms of all vectors; if you change the norm of any vector, you are by definition changing the metric.
 
  • #81
DaleSpam said:
I don't know why you keep making this absurd statement when we have already discussed the fact that radiation defines the timelike direction too. Radiation and the metric identify timelike curves every bit as well as matter.
But as I said in the post before that, when we do the symmetry operation, we change all vectors. So the tangent vector of the path of the beam of light would also change.
 
  • #82
PeterDonis said:
This is a logical contradiction. The metric determines the norms of all vectors; if you change the norm of any vector, you are by definition changing the metric.
no, I'm saying that I change the vectors, but leave the metric alone.
 
  • #83
BruceW said:
But as I said in the post before that, when we do the symmetry operation, we change all vectors. So the tangent vector of the path of the beam of light would also change.
Then that will change the metric. You cannot change the path of a pulse of light this way without changing the metric.
 
Last edited:
  • #84
ah wait, you're right. the arc length of a beam of light could become non-zero under my 'symmetry operation'. So the system definitely doesn't stay the same... wow, that was a fairly simple way to show that the timelike curves are not arbitrary. Thanks man. yeah, I guess I was wrong about that.

Now I'm trying to think of what that means / absorb the message. The null curves tell us which dimension is the timelike one?

we already briefly mentioned a beam of light. But because I only talked about one beam of light, that would not specify the timelike dimension. As long as we have two beams going in different directions, then that tells us the timelike dimension.

So as long as we have a way to identify null curves, then we know the timelike dimension. And I think it is OK to say that generally, we always can identify the null curves.

edit: and thanks to PeterDonis for continuing to try to get through to me. It did help that you kept asking me to think more mathematically / be less hand-wavey about what I was saying.
 
  • #85
BruceW said:
As long as we have two beams going in different directions, then that tells us the timelike dimension.

Exactly.

BruceW said:
I think it is OK to say that generally, we always can identify the null curves.

Yes. That's why you often see people talking about the light cones (which are just the sets of null vectors at each event) as the things to focus on when you're trying to analyze the structure of a spacetime.

BruceW said:
thanks to PeterDonis for continuing to try to get through to me. It did help that you kept asking me to think more mathematically / be less hand-wavey about what I was saying.

You're welcome! I'm glad it's clear now.
 
  • #86
BruceW said:
wow, that was a fairly simple way to show that the timelike curves are not arbitrary. Thanks man. yeah, I guess I was wrong about that.

Now I'm trying to think of what that means / absorb the message. The null curves tell us which dimension is the timelike one?

we already briefly mentioned a beam of light. But because I only talked about one beam of light, that would not specify the timelike dimension. As long as we have two beams going in different directions, then that tells us the timelike dimension.

So as long as we have a way to identify null curves, then we know the timelike dimension. And I think it is OK to say that generally, we always can identify the null curves.

In a (n+1)-dimensional spacetime,
the thing that distinguishes "timelike" is
the causality [i.e. the causal-future ordering, a partial-ordering] defined by the light-cone structure (and a conventional choice of which direction is "future").
No analogous ordering exists for the spacelike-directions [unless n=1].
[This is similar to my earlier post about no-closed-timelike curves vs closed-spacelike curves in (3+1)-Minkowski.]
One could argue that there is a symmetry between timelike and spacelike for (1+1)-Minkowski.

In (3+1)-spacetimes, the sum of two non-parallel future-directed null vectors is a future-timelike vector.

However, the null-curves may not be enough in more exotic examples like (2+2) or (n+2) or even degenerate cases (n+m+p) for (-,+,0). The light-cone structure [the ordering] is lost. One would still have different types of tangent-vectors... but a label of "time" to one of them would no longer be appropriate.
 
  • #87
edit: I see Robphy posted while I was writing...

from BruceW:
The null curves tell us which dimension is the timelike one?

What does this mean?

Shouldn't this read "The null curve tell us which dimension is the LIGHT-LIKE one.."??
 
  • #88
Naty1 said:
edit: I see Robphy posted while I was writing...

from BruceW:

What does this mean?

Shouldn't this read "The null curve tell us which dimension is the LIGHT-LIKE one.."??
The null curves are light like, but they also form the boundary between timelike and spacelike. So curves on one side are timelike and curves on the other side are lightlike.
 
  • #89
they also form the boundary between timelike and spacelike. So curves on one side are timelike and curves on the other side are lightlike.


yes, I get that, but can you tell from null curve alone which is which?? That's what BruceW seems to have posted.
 
  • #90
Naty1 said:
yes, I get that, but can you tell from null curve alone which is which?? That's what BruceW seems to have posted.

Yes; as BruceW said, two null vectors pointing in different directions define a timelike vector. (Just take the vector sum of the two null vectors; it will be timelike. For example, the two null vectors ##(1, 1, 0, 0)## and ##(1, 0, 1, 0)## add up to ##(2, 1, 1, 0)##, which is timelike.)
 
  • #91
Naty1 said:
yes, I get that, but can you tell from null curve alone which is which?? That's what BruceW seems to have posted.
If you have the set of all null geodesics passing through an event in space-time, you can pass to the tangent space at that point using the exponential map to get a cone (null cone) and the interior of the cone will let you determine the set of all time-like geodesics through that point and the exterior of the cone will let you determine the set of all space-like geodesics through that point because the null cone partitions the tangent space at that point into space-like vectors (exterior), null vectors (cone itself), and time-like vectors (interior).
 
Last edited:
  • #92
PeterDonis said:
Yes; as BruceW said, two null vectors pointing in different directions define a timelike vector. (Just take the vector sum of the two null vectors; it will be timelike. For example, the two null vectors ##(1, 1, 0, 0)## and ##(1, 0, 1, 0)## add up to ##(2, 1, 1, 0)##, which is timelike.)

The null-vectors need to be both future-pointing or both past-pointing for their sum to be timelike... as noted in my earlier post.
Future-pointing-null plus past-pointing-null can be spacelike.
 
  • #93
robphy said:
The null-vectors need to be both future-pointing or both past-pointing for their sum to be timelike... as noted in my earlier post.
Future-pointing-null plus past-pointing-null can be spacelike.

Ah, yes, good point. At least I chose an example that met this requirement. :wink:
 
  • #94
Below the event horizon, the radial spatial dimension is said to become timelike. It has the special property that objects can can only travel in one direction (towards the singularity). Outside the event horizon, the time dimension is of course timelike and it also has the special quality that objects can only travel in one direction (towards the future). Doesn't anyone else find that curious? It suggests that the timelike dimension is the only dimension that has this unique one way property.

Conversely, the time dimension below the event horizon becomes spacelike and it is OK for objects (and light) to go backwards or forwards in coordinate time in that location.
 
  • #95
Is it? Aren't we ourselves placing the physical restriction that material particles must travel on future-directed time-like curves?
 
  • #96
yuiop said:
Below the event horizon, the radial spatial dimension is said to become timelike. It has the special property that objects can can only travel in one direction (towards the singularity).

But there is also the "white hole" solution, the time reverse of the black hole, which inside its horizon has the property that objects can only travel along timelike curves in one direction, *away* from the singularity. So the time symmetry is still there; it's just that you have to look at the full set of solutions to see it. What picks out the "black hole" solution as the one we actually use is experimental observation: we observe plenty of objects that are good candidates to be black holes, but we've never observed any object that's a good candidate to be a white hole.

(Similarly, the expanding FRW solution that we use to describe our universe has a time reverse, the contracting FRW solution. We pick the expanding solution for actual use because we experimentally observe the universe to be expanding.)
 
  • #97
yuiop: oh, good point...I forgot about event horizons...'timelike' on both sides...[if that is conventional terminology]

But I think all of you resolved my question about BruceW's post...which was

The null curves tell us which dimension is the timelike one?

and which I did not 'like'...because while the curves do

form the boundary between timelike and spacelike.

null curve ALONE don't distinguish which is which ; one needs an additional piece of information to determine spacelike vs timelike...like two null vectors pointing in the same direction...

And Robphy post...
If you have the set of all null geodesics passing through an event in space-time, you can pass to the tangent space at that point using the exponential map to get a cone (null cone) and the interior of the cone will let you determine the set of all time-like geodesics through that point and the exterior of the cone...

is another 'twist' I hadn't thought about...

thanks...nice insights into spacetime which I found very helpful...
 
  • #98
WannabeNewton said:
the interior of the cone will let you determine the set of all time-like geodesics through that point and the exterior of the cone will let you determine the set of all space-like geodesics through that point

Is there a slick way to capture how the "interior" and "exterior" of the cone are defined, in terms of the null vectors themselves?
 
  • #99
Causal order.
 
  • #100
PeterDonis said:
Is there a slick way to capture how the "interior" and "exterior" of the cone are defined, in terms of the null vectors themselves?
I was thinking of it geometrically but I'm not sure if it's slick in any way. If we take an event ##p##, we can find an orthonormal basis ##\{e_{\mu}\}## for ##T_p M## so that ##g_{\mu\nu}(p) = \eta_{\mu\nu}## hence the set of all null vectors at ##p## will be given by ##S = \{\lambda = \lambda^{\mu}e_{\mu}:-(\lambda^0)^2 + (\lambda^1)^2 + (\lambda^2)^2 + (\lambda^3)^2 = 0\}##. This is equivalent to a cone in Minkowski space-time with vertex at the origin and in the same way as in Minkowski space-time, the "interior" would just be the set of all points inside of the cone so defined by ##S## and the "exterior" would just be the set of all points outside of the cone so defined by ##S##.
 

Similar threads

Back
Top