Is Wave Theory the Key to Understanding All Physical Phenomena?

  • Thread starter eoghan
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Wave
In summary, the conversation discusses the idea of classical mechanics being rewritten in terms of waves and whether there are any phenomena that require a corpuscular view to be explained. The concept of fundamental things in physics and their relationship to mathematical abstractions is also explored. The conversation concludes with a discussion of different interpretations of quantum mechanics and their predictions, particularly the Broglie-Bohm interpretation which is considered to be a different quantized theory.
  • #1
eoghan
207
7
Hi! A bullet follows a parabolic trajectory when fired in a gravitational field. I've read a text where this trajectory was derived supposing the bullet as a wave. So, can't the classical mechanics be rewritten supposing that everything is a wave? Or, in other words, is there a phenomenon which requires a corpuscular view to be explained?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Yes, classical mechanics is recovered in the appropriate limit of quantum mechanics.
 
  • #3
eoghan said:
Hi! A bullet follows a parabolic trajectory when fired in a gravitational field. I've read a text where this trajectory was derived supposing the bullet as a wave. So, can't the classical mechanics be rewritten supposing that everything is a wave? Or, in other words, is there a phenomenon which requires a corpuscular view to be explained?

Yes there is: electron position can be ascertained with unlimited precision. This would not be possible in a pure wave view.

However, this should not be used as a proof that particles are not waves. The controlling rule is the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle. An electron can act as a particle, wave, or a combination of the two. (Interference is something that waves do that particles cannot. An electron can be made to demonstrate wave behavior by exhibiting interference.)
 
  • #4
eoghan said:
Hi! A bullet follows a parabolic trajectory when fired in a gravitational field. I've read a text where this trajectory was derived supposing the bullet as a wave. So, can't the classical mechanics be rewritten supposing that everything is a wave? Or, in other words, is there a phenomenon which requires a corpuscular view to be explained?

Yes, I agree with you that everything can be described in terms of classical waves (hopefully even QM).

But a wave of what?
 
  • #5
Fundamental things do not consist of something.
It is like asking 'what numbers consist of'?
 
  • #6
eoghan said:
Hi! A bullet follows a parabolic trajectory when fired in a gravitational field. I've read a text where this trajectory was derived supposing the bullet as a wave. So, can't the classical mechanics be rewritten supposing that everything is a wave? Or, in other words, is there a phenomenon which requires a corpuscular view to be explained?

Are you referring to the Hamilton-Jacobi version of classical mechanics? As far as I know this is the only known way to write CM in terms of waves.

Essentially the problem of dynamics as defined by Hamilton's equations can be formulated in terms of a partial differential equation determining the evolution of a field [tex]S(q,t)[/tex]. The role of this [tex]S[/tex] function is to generate a momentum (vector) field on configuration space. Integral curves along the field are possible trajectories of the [tex]N[/tex]-particle system. The 'wave' therefore refers to an ensemble of identical systems rather than a single trajectory.
 
  • #7
DaleSpam said:
Yes, classical mechanics is recovered in the appropriate limit of quantum mechanics.

Not in orthodox QM - that's one of the main problems with it.

However, you can easily do it with the Broglie-Bohm interpretation of QM (how did you know I was going to say that?).
 
  • #8
DrChinese said:
Yes there is: electron position can be ascertained with unlimited precision. This would not be possible in a pure wave view.

I don't know what you mean by this.
 
  • #9
Fundamental things are such as long as a more fundamental description is found. I mean that could not exist fundamental things in physics, that is an indivisible and elementary atom of nature. On the contrary if fundamental things really exist you are right.

Concerning the number I don't think we can speak about fundamental things in a physical way. The numbers, as every mathematical objects, are abstractions that we associate sometimes to apples and sometimes to stars. The fundamental things in physics are the things that we describe with some mathematical abstraction. If the world would be described in terms of elementary waves, these waves would be the fundamental things that we describes in terms of sin and cos.
 
  • #10
zenith8 said:
Not in orthodox QM - that's one of the main problems with it.

However, you can easily do it with the Broglie-Bohm interpretation of QM (how did you know I was going to say that?).
Different interpretations of a theory, by definition, do not make different predictions (otherwise they would be different theories instead of different interpretations). If you can recover the predictions of classical mechanics with one interpretation of QM then you can do so with all interpretations.

That said, I have no problem with the Broglie-Bohm interpretation, and in fact recommend that people learn all interpretations and use each when convenient instead of restricting themselves to only one.
 
  • #11
DaleSpam said:
Different interpretations of a theory, by definition, do not make different predictions (otherwise they would be different theories instead of different interpretations).

De Broglie-Bohm is indeed a different theory; it is based on a different set of axioms to orthodox QM and it makes different predictions which in principle - though with great difficulty - could be observed (in the so-called quantum non-equilibrium case). I apologize for my loose language.

If you can recover the predictions of classical mechanics with one interpretation of QM then you can do so with all interpretations.

Leaving the language issue aside, it is an unfortunate fact that the recovery of the classical limit require you to (a) specify your ontology (what exists), and (b) to include particles in that ontology. Orthodox QM does neither; one cannot recover the classical limit using that approach. It is (relatively) trivial in de Broglie-Bohm.
 
  • #12
zenith8 said:
De Broglie-Bohm is indeed a different theory; it is based on a different set of axioms to orthodox QM
That doesn't matter much. It is always possible to choose a different set of axioms for the same theory.
zenith8 said:
and it makes different predictions which in principle - though with great difficulty - could be observed (in the so-called quantum non-equilibrium case).
That is very interesting, and I was not aware of it. In that case De Broglie-Bohm is not an interpretation of QM but a different quantized theory. However, if the differences are so difficult to predict then obviously they must not be relevant in the classical limit.
zenith8 said:
the recovery of the classical limit require you to (a) specify your ontology (what exists)
This is most certainly not the case. Questions of ontology are irrelevant to questions of predictions. The quintessential example is Special Relativity and Lorentz Aether Theory, which are two different interpretations of the same theory. They have decidedly different ontologies, but both produce the same experimental predictions in all cases and both recover classical mechanics in the appropriate limit. Different theories need not have any ontological similarities whatsoever in order to arrive to the same prediction in some limit.

In any case, nothing you have said so far lends any credence whatsoever to your assertion that classical mechanics is not recovered from QM in the appropriate limit. Momentum is conserved as is energy, the expectation values behave exactly as you would expect the corresponding classical variables to behave in the classical limit. Hamilton's equations work at both scales and lead directly to Newton's laws which define classical mechanics.
 
Last edited:
  • #13
DrChinese said:
Yes there is: electron position can be ascertained with unlimited precision. This would not be possible in a pure wave view.

The quesion was about 'everything', including measuring equipment and observers.
 
  • #14
eoghan said:
Hi! A bullet follows a parabolic trajectory when fired in a gravitational field. I've read a text where this trajectory was derived supposing the bullet as a wave. So, can't the classical mechanics be rewritten supposing that everything is a wave? Or, in other words, is there a phenomenon which requires a corpuscular view to be explained?

Yes there is. Light has some behavior that is particle-like. This becomes obvious if you have light levels that are low enough so that you can see the invididual light particles (i.e. photons). If you every see the world through night vision googles or CCD's, you can actually see invididual light particles hitting the glasses.

Also solar photovoltic cells work when invididual light particles hit electrons. What this means is that if you shine red light on a solar panel it won't knock out electrons.
 
  • #15
DaleSpam said:
That is very interesting, and I was not aware of it. In that case De Broglie-Bohm is not an interpretation of QM but a different quantized theory. However, if the differences are so difficult to predict then obviously they must not be relevant in the classical limit.This is most certainly not the case. Questions of ontology are irrelevant to questions of predictions.

It's not difficult to predict, it's just difficult to measure. Because particles and waves (which are both supposed to exist in this theory) are logically independent entities, then the former need not be distributed as the square of the wave as in Born's rule. It can be shown that they just approach that distribution under a dynamical equilibrium process.

Interestingly, it is evidently a mathematical reformulation of QM rather than an interpretation because one can do unique calculations with it. A particular nice example is in calculating the propagator - i.e. the probability amplitude for a particle moving from one place to another after some time - by integrating Lagrangians along trajectories a la Feynmann's path integral version of QM. Professor Feynman sums integrals of the classical Lagrangian along all possible paths in the entire universe. If you include the potential function of the deBB quantum force in the Lagrangian, then you can achieve exactly the same thing by summing integrals of the resulting quantum Lagrangian over er.. precisely one path - the one the electron actually follows - rather than an infinite number of them. Gotta be an improvement.

The quintessential example is Special Relativity and Lorentz Aether Theory, which are two different interpretations of the same theory. They have decidedly different ontologies, but both produce the same experimental predictions in all cases and both recover classical mechanics in the appropriate limit. Different theories need not have any ontological similarities whatsoever in order to arrive to the same prediction in some limit.

Yes - I seem to recall it was me who kept bugging you about Lorentz theory about a year ago. I don't think you convinced anyone then about the role of ontologies either.

In any case, nothing you have said so far lends any credence whatsoever to your assertion that classical mechanics is not recovered from QM in the appropriate limit. Momentum is conserved as is energy, the expectation values behave exactly as you would expect the corresponding classical variables to behave in the classical limit. Hamilton's equations work at both scales and lead directly to Newton's laws which define classical mechanics.

Nope. I'm afraid you're not allowed to deduce a classical theory of matter from a statistical theory of observation, i.e. from any solution of the Schroedinger equation in any limit, even well-localized ones (packets) that remain so over time. You have to supplement the pure theory of linear fields by a physical ontological postulate (like in de Broglie-Bohm) or you can't claim that a material object is at definite x independent of measurement as in classical mechanics.

And anyway, you can only pretend to get away with it by presupposing what you want to define. Remember in standard QM, only the results of measurements and possibly the wave function exist. Orthodox QM presupposes the validity of classical concepts since it is only in this way that you can unambiguously communicate experimental results in the quantum domain. We then use the so-called correspondence principle which demonstrates the consistency of quantum theory with this presupposition.

The correspondence principle is a vague notion stating that, in effect the behaviour of quantum systems reproduces classical physics under suitable conditions (e.g. in limit of large size or large quantum numbers or - ludicrously - as [tex]\hbar \rightarrow 0 [/tex]). With the Schroedinger equation interpreted probabilistically, Ehrenfest's theorem shows that Newton's laws hold on average, in that the quantum statistical expectation values of the position and momentum operators obey Newton's laws (if V varies slowly over the wave packet). However, again this is a presupposition: which operators are chosen to correspond to physical quantities or measurements? Guess what - only those ones that reproduce classical mechanics in the limit.

This has ludicrous consequences for 'measurement' - as absolutely any interpretation which supplies the electrons with a trajectory will show you. One trajectory that quantum particles behaving in a quantum manner absolutely do not have is the Newtonian one; working out the expectation value of the momentum operator gives you the instantaneous momentum only in the classical limit. The very word 'measurement' implies that you are measuring some property of the particle that existed before the experiment but you are not. If you analyze it the momentum operator just gives you one particular component of the stress tensor of the wave field, and has nothing to do with the momentum of anything (which puts all those endless discussions of Heisenberg's uncertainty principle into perspective). It's all a comforting but false superconstruction. Remember Einstein: 'Your theory will one day get you into hot water.When it comes to observation, you behave as if everything can be left as it was, that is, as if you could use the old descriptive language.' Heisenberg et al. got away with labelling the old Einstein as a bumbling old fool back then, but many people have since realized how sharp Einstein was being about this.

To conclude the game, I need only quote Bohm himself. As standard QM only reproduces CM statistically and because the statistical interpretation only gives probabilities of different classical outcomes, Bohr argued that CM does not emerge from QM in the same way that e.g. CM emerges as approximation of special relativity at small v. He argued that CM exists independently of QM and cannot be derived from it - it is inappropriate to understand observer experiences using purely QM notions like wave functions as different states of experience of an observer are defined classically and do not have a QM analog.

So to sum up, you cannot logically deduce a model of substantial matter and its motion from an algorithm which has no such concepts at all (i.e. it makes no statements as to what matter is). This leads to a further problem: orthodox QM is practically successful but seemingly fundamentally ill-defined. Bohr postulates the existence of classical 'measuring devices' (in deBB theory, the instruments themselves emerge out of the limit). However, in the Bohrian view, there is no clear dividing line between 'microscopic indefiniteness' and the definite states of the classical macroscopic realm. What happens to the definite states of the everyday macroscopic world as one goes to smaller scales? Where does the macroscopic definiteness (where 'real' means something) give way to microscopic indefiniteness (where it doesn't)?. Does the transition occur somewhere between pollen grains and macromolecules, and if so, where? What side of the line is a virus on? In orthodox QM, there is no answer.

This is already getting too long, so I will just briefly summarize the deBB approach to the classical limit. In this theory there are two forces (the classical one, and the 'quantum' one - the latter resulting from the wave field pushing the particles around). The classical domain is where the wave component of matter becomes passive and exerts no influence on the corpuscular component, i.e. the state of the particle is independent of the state of the field. So we ask how does the state or context dependence characteristic of the quantum domain turn into the state independence at the classical level? Answer: when the actual trajectories look Newtonian, which is when the quantum Hamilton-Jacobi equation (which arises - in addition to a simple continuity equation - from splitting the complex Schroedinger equation into two real ones) reduces directly to the classical Hamilton-Jacobi equation (a standard way of rewriting classical mechanics in terms of waves - see my response to the OP). Under the right circumstances the force on the particle then goes from [tex]-\nabla (V+Q)[/tex] to [tex]-\nabla V[/tex] (here [tex]Q[/tex] is the potential energy function of the quantum force) and the trajectories become Newtonian. Limits like m going to infinity or whatever are not enough; this must be in addition to a proper choice of state.

You're going to argue with me aren't you, because you always do. Go on then..
 
Last edited:
  • #16
An ontology for quantum mechanics is irrelevant in the question of whether or not it captures the classical case in the limit. To answer that question, the thing that matters is that one can specify an ontology for classical mechanics in terms of the abstract mathematical theory of quantum mechanics.
 
  • #17
Hurkyl said:
An ontology for quantum mechanics is irrelevant in the question of whether or not it captures the classical case in the limit. To answer that question, the thing that matters is that one can specify an ontology for classical mechanics in terms of the abstract mathematical theory of quantum mechanics.

Ah, God how could I not have seen that? [slaps forehead and hurls himself from the top of a high building].
 
  • #18
twofish-quant said:
Yes there is. Light has some behavior that is particle-like. This becomes obvious if you have light levels that are low enough so that you can see the invididual light particles (i.e. photons). If you every see the world through night vision googles or CCD's, you can actually see invididual light particles hitting the glasses.

Also solar photovoltic cells work when invididual light particles hit electrons. What this means is that if you shine red light on a solar panel it won't knock out electrons.

So it's obvious that light is a particle. But now let's ask if it's a wave? I see no wave properties! For example you say interference show that light is a wave. But I see no interference. If I shine photons at a slit or double slit I observe a classical interference pattern, right? Wrong! I observe a bunch of photon particles landing on my detector! Now it turns out if I collect a bunch of impact positions and add them all up, lo and behold the pattern that results is exactly the same mathematical function as a wave diffraction pattern. But this pattern is made up of particle impacts NOT wave intensities! It is NOT a wave property at all. Who knows why such trajectories form into wave solutions when averaged over large numbers?

And it's worse than that. Light transmits energy through the empty vacuum of "empty" space. Particles can transmit energy through "nothing at all" but waves cannot. Waves need a medium to transmit energy. And it gets still worse. If I shine light on a photcell, we find the energy is transferred almost instantaneously...as a particle would. A wave would take TIME to transfer an equal amount of energy and it goes on and on.

So I put it to you. How can light be a "wave only" phenomena? It can't even be a wave and particle phenomena! Where are the waves? Well sure, there are "probability waves", but what are they? What is the medium they travel in? What generates probability waves? How do they "collapse" into sudden manifestation of objects? What is going on? Obviously there is lots of hand-waving and nobody with a clue. The fact that a QM wave theory gives correct answers does not prove that such waves exist. The fact that the statistical trajectory landings we just talked about form wave solutions when averaged means that it is not surprising that wave equations give "correct" answers. But it all explains nothing.
 
  • #19
bjacoby said:
Who knows why such trajectories form into wave solutions when averaged over large numbers?

Our very own Louis-Victor-Pierre-Raymond, 7th duc de Broglie and Professor David Bohm!

I thank you.
 
  • #20
bjacoby said:
I see no wave properties!

Just to get the facts straight: There is plenty of evidence for the wave character of light. See for example:

E. Goulielmakis, et al.
Direct Measurement of Light Waves
Science 305, 1267 (2004)
http://www.sciencemag.org/cgi/content/abstract/305/5688/1267
 
  • #21
zenith8 said:
the behaviour of quantum systems reproduces classical physics under suitable conditions (e.g. in limit of large size or large quantum numbers or - ludicrously - as [tex]\hbar \rightarrow 0 [/tex]). ...

Ehrenfest's theorem shows that Newton's laws hold on average, in that the quantum statistical expectation values of the position and momentum operators obey Newton's laws (if V varies slowly over the wave packet). ...

which operators are chosen to correspond to physical quantities or measurements? Guess what - only those ones that reproduce classical mechanics in the limit. ...

standard QM only reproduces CM statistically ...

You're going to argue with me aren't you
Why should I argue? You clearly agree with me about my original point. You just think the standard interpretation is "ludicrous", and I'm fine with that.
 
  • #22
conway said:
I don't know what you mean by this.

Because waves are spread out and do not exist in the limit of a point. So if an electron were a wave, then trying to isolate it to a progressively smaller volume should not work. (Again I am not asserting an electron is purely a particle either; simply stating that it is the HUP that describes wave vs. particle behavior.)
 
  • #23
bjacoby said:
So I put it to you. How can light be a "wave only" phenomena? It can't even be a wave and particle phenomena! Where are the waves? Well sure, there are "probability waves", but what are they? What is the medium they travel in? What generates probability waves? How do they "collapse" into sudden manifestation of objects? What is going on? Obviously there is lots of hand-waving and nobody with a clue. The fact that a QM wave theory gives correct answers does not prove that such waves exist.

You have ventured into the realm of the semantic at this point. Clearly, the standard view is that light has both particle *and* wave nature depending on how it is observed. But it is no more possible to single out the particle view as preferred as it is to single out the wave view as preferred. Such a decision will necessarily depend on your definitions - none of which will change the underlying character of the actual physics.

The physics, of course, being the language of QM. So your criticism is really a critique of the theory; that critique would be readily accepted if there were a better theory offered. Barring that, we simply return to where we were: we don't know why the math works as it does. I don't see that as much of a criticism; we have the same situation with General Relativity too. We have that with any fundamental theory in fact.
 
  • #24
DrChinese said:
Because waves are spread out and do not exist in the limit of a point. So if an electron were a wave, then trying to isolate it to a progressively smaller volume should not work. (Again I am not asserting an electron is purely a particle either; simply stating that it is the HUP that describes wave vs. particle behavior.)

I wonder if you can come up with a specific experimental scenario which illustrates this difficulty.
 
  • #25
conway said:
I wonder if you can come up with a specific experimental scenario which illustrates this difficulty.

Well, I would say that any experiment in which the particle nature is observed, you will see the disappearance of wave effects. The quantum eraser experiments are a good example, as you go from wave to particle view and see interference appear/disappear.
 
  • #26
DrChinese said:
Well, I would say that any experiment in which the particle nature is observed, you will see the disappearance of wave effects. The quantum eraser experiments are a good example, as you go from wave to particle view and see interference appear/disappear.

I thought you were going to give an example of how to confine an electron to a volume too small for a wave.
 
  • #27
conway said:
I thought you were going to give an example of how to confine an electron to a volume too small for a wave.

Well, how small is small enough? Obviously, we know that electrons are point-like to the limit of our precision. So I guess you would need to explain how a wave can go through both slits of a double slit apparatus (i.e. a much larger separation) and still be confined to a very small point-like volume at other times. Quantum particles can do this because they are neither wave nor particle exclusively, but are described by the HUP.
 
  • #28
DrChinese said:
Obviously, we know that electrons are point-like to the limit of our precision.

I don't think I've asked for anything else except for an explanation of how we supposedly know this.
 
  • #29
conway said:
I don't think I've asked for anything else except for an explanation of how we supposedly know this.

Here is one I got from a PhysicsForums thread:

http://www.iop.org/EJ/abstract/1402-4896/1988/T22/016/

"From the close agreement of experimental and theoretical g-values a new, 10^4 × smaller, value for the electron radius, Rg < 10^-20 cm, may be extracted. Other important results are: confinement of the individual positron, Priscilla, for 3 months, a tenfold suppression of the natural width of the cyclotron resonance, detection of an isomeric (cyclotron-excited) state via mass-spectroscopy, isolation and continuous detection of an individual proton, confinement of approx 100 antiprotons slowed to approx 3000 eV, ..."

So a radius of less than 10^-13 nm, this was in 1987. By comparison, the associated wavelength of the electron is about 12 x 10^-3 nm. That is roughly 100 billion times larger.

If you look for waves, you see waves. If you look for particles, you see particles. Experiment in close agreement with an 80 year old theory, featuring the HUP.
 
  • #30
conway said:
I don't think I've asked for anything else except for an explanation of how we supposedly know this.

It's actually quite fun. You have throw two electrons at each other, and see how they bounce of each other, and they behave exactly like two point particles interacting with each other.

Note that this is *not* the case with protons and neutrons. If you throw two protons and neutrons at each other hard enough, then they stop behaving like point particles and they start acting as if there is stuff on the inside of them (i.e. quarks).
 
  • #31
DrChinese said:
Here is one I got from a PhysicsForums thread:

http://www.iop.org/EJ/abstract/1402-4896/1988/T22/016/

"From the close agreement of experimental and theoretical g-values a new, 10^4 × smaller, value for the electron radius, Rg < 10^-20 cm, may be extracted...

I don't believe this answers my question. I asked how we supposedly know that an electron can be confined to an arbitrarily small volume. You have given me a reference for the experimentally determined electron radius. I really can't make the connection.
 
  • #32
Just to keep this on track, the original statement by Dr. Chinese was to the effect that the position of an electron can be determined to arbitrary precision. I am still asking what this means and how we supposedly know it to be true.
 
  • #33
DrChinese said:
So I guess you would need to explain how a wave can go through both slits of a double slit apparatus (i.e. a much larger separation) and still be confined to a very small point-like volume at other times.

Because there is a wave and an accompanying particle, rather than one thing which is somehow both. I mean, is this just too simple or something?
 
  • #34
twofish-quant said:
It's actually quite fun. You have throw two electrons at each other, and see how they bounce of each other, and they behave exactly like two point particles interacting with each other.
Well, for correctness, I think you should mention the fact that, however, you need a quantum mechanical description, so you cannot avoid using wavefunctions (= also wave description).
 
  • #35
lightarrow said:
Well, for correctness, I think you should mention the fact that, however, you need a quantum mechanical description, so you cannot avoid using wavefunctions (= also wave description).

Exactly.
 

Similar threads

Replies
26
Views
2K
Replies
12
Views
4K
  • Classical Physics
Replies
10
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
33
Views
3K
Replies
17
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
7
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
4K
Replies
46
Views
7K
Back
Top