philiprdutton said:
Thanks for the input. So, it sounds as if the axiomatic Peano system basically builds the "structure" that we find in the "number line."
[T or F] The number line doesn't exist until after an axiomatic system is written to create the structure.
[T or F] You can't have a number without the ability to know what it is in terms of it's successor and/or it's predecessor.
[T or F] You can't have a the notion of a "number" separated from operations like addition/multiplication EVEN if you do not define those operations in your axioms.
[T or F] A system that can give us, in order, "1,2,3,4,5,6..." can also be modified to only give us, "blip,blip,blip,blip,..." However, given the modified system, we do not know if "the tape is moving or the tape is not moving". (I am making a play on the Turing machine when I use the word "tape")
Thanks for the input. If someone can help me with the above T/F statements then I would be very grateful and will be ready to close this thread (much to everyone's relief I am sure!). Obviously, I need to go study... : )
Maybe you can define something structurally equivalent to the set of natural numbers this way...
Let U be any infinite set (which could mean, for instance, that there is a one-to-one correspondence between U and at least one of its
proper subsets). Such a set exists in ZF by the axiom of infinity.
Pick out any element of U. Let's call it u*. Now let S be any function with domain U and range contained in U with the following conditions:
1. u* is
not in the range of S
2. S has
no fixed points (i.e., for all u in U, S(u) is not u)
(u* is going to behave like the number 1 and S like the successor function.)
Now for another definition. A subset A of U is called
inductive (or S-inductive because it depends on S) iff the following conditions hold:
1. u* is in A and
2. for all a in A, S(a) is in A.
Let N* be the intersection of all inductive subsets of U. This is going to be what behaves like the set of natural numbers. I think N* will just be the orbit of u*:
{u*, S(u*), S(S(u*)), S(S(S(u*))), S(S(S(S(u*)))), S(S(S(S(S(u*))))), ...}.
N* certainly won't be like N at all if the orbit of u* is finite, so let's add a third condition to S:
1. u* is
not in the range of S
2. S has
no fixed points (i.e., for all u in U, S(u) is not u)
3. All elements in the set {u*, S(u*), S(S(u*)), S(S(S(u*))), S(S(S(S(u*)))), S(S(S(S(S(u*))))), ...} are different.
Now define a relation
on N*, call it R, which will behave like less than or equal to:
(x,y) is in R iff y is in the orbit of x. In other words, (x,y) is in R iff either y=x or y=S(x) or y=S(S(x)) or y=S(S(S(x))) or ... .
I think then that (N, <=) is structurally like (N*, R) in that if we define a function from N to N*, called f, as f(n) is the (n-1)st iterate of u* under S, then f would be a one-to-one correspondence
and "relation preserving," i.e., for all n1 and n2 in N, then n1 <= n2
iff R( f(n1), f(n2) ).
If this is true, then for any given U, S with the stated properties on U, then the intersection of all inductive sets would behave like the set of natural numbers.
Incidentally, when the axiom says 1 is a natural number, I'm wondering what 1 is. One way to make that work is to define 1 to be the set whose element is the empty set and for all sets a, define the successor of a to be the union of a with the set whose element is a.