999

Is There a Rigorous Proof Of 1 = 0.999…?

Yes.

First, we have not addressed what 0.999… actually means. So it’s best first to describe what on earth the notation [tex]b_0.b_1b_2b_3…[/tex] means. The way mathematicians define this thing is

[tex]b_0.b_1b_2b_3…=\sum_{n=0}^{+\infty}{\frac{b_n}{10^n}}[/tex]

So, in particular, we have that

[tex]0.999…=\sum_{n=1}^{+\infty}{\frac{9}{10^n}}[/tex]

But all of this doesn’t really make any sense until we define what the right-hand side means. There is an infinite sum there, but what does that mean? Well, we put

[tex]S_k=\sum_{n=1}^{k}{\frac{9}{10^n}} \ ,[/tex]

then we have a finite sum. So, for example
[tex]S_1=0.9, \ ~S_2=0.99, \ ~S_3=0.999, \ etc.[/tex]
So, in some way, we want to take the limit of this sequence.

Let’s consider a particularly simple sequence to illustrate the idea behind the definition of a limit of a sequence: 1/2, 1/3, 1/4,… The terms in this sequence get smaller and smaller. You might think that it’s obvious that it goes to 0, or that it’s obvious that a smart mathematician can prove that it goes to 0, but it’s not. It’s impossible to even attempt a proof until we have defined what it means for something to go to 0. So we have to define what the statement “1/2, 1/3, 1/4,… goes to 0” means, before we can attempt to prove that it’s true.

This is the standard definition: “1/n goes to 0” means that “for every positive real number [itex]\epsilon[/itex], there’s a positive integer N, such that for all integers n such that [itex]n\geq N[/itex], we have [itex]|1/n| < \epsilon[/itex]”. With this definition in place, it’s quite easy to prove that “1/n goes to 0” is a true statement. What I want you to see here, is that we chose this definition to make sure that this statement would be true. The first mathematicians who thought about how to define the limit of a sequence might have briefly considered definitions that make the statement “1/n goes to 0” false, but they would have dismissed those definitions as irrelevant, because they fail to capture the idea of a limit that they already understood on an intuitive level.

So the real reason why 1/n goes to 0 is that we wanted it to! Similar comments hold for the sequence of partial sums that define 0.999… It goes to 1, because we have defined the concepts “0.999….”, “sum of infinitely many terms”, and “limit of a sequence” in ways that make 0.999…=1. Can we define number systems such that 1=0.999… does not hold? Of course! But these number systems are not as useful, because they don’t conform to our intuition about limits and numbers.

Now that we know what a limit and an infinite sum is, let me give a fully rigourous proof to the equality 1=0.999… This proof is due to Euler and it appears in the 1770’s edition of “Elements of algebra”.
We know that

[tex]0.999…=\sum_{n=1}^{+\infty}{ \frac{9}{10^n} } = \frac{9}{10} + \frac{9}{10^2} + \frac{9}{10^3} +…[/tex]

This sum is a special kind of sum, namely, it’s a geometric sum. For (infinite) geometric sums, we can find its limit easily:

Let
[tex]x=\frac{1}{10}+\frac{1}{10^2}+\frac{1}{10^3}+…[/tex]
Then
[tex]9x=0.999…[/tex]

But, we also have [itex]10x=1+\frac{1}{10}+\frac{1}{10^2}+…[/itex], so [itex]10x-x=1[/itex].

This implies that [itex]x=\frac{1}{9}[/itex].

Hence,
[tex]0.999…=9x=1[/tex]
Does this proof look familiar? It should! It is essentially the same as Proof #2 in the previous post. The only difference is that every step is now justified by operations with limits.

The following forum members have contributed to this FAQ:
AlephZero
Fredrik
micromass
tiny-tim
vela

To forum post

9 replies
Newer Comments »
  1. WWGD
    WWGD says:

    You can also use, though not as nice,  the perspective of the Reals as a metric space, together with the Archimedean Principle:  then d(x,y)=0 iff x=y. Let then ## x=1 , y=0.9999….  ##Then ##d(x,y)=|x-y| ## can be made indefinitely small ( by going farther along the string of 9's ), forcing ## |x-y|=0## , forcing  ##x=y ##. More formally, for any ##\epsilon >0 ##, we can make ##|x-y|< \epsilon ##

  2. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    I can show that whatever the meaning of the number 0.0000000 => 00001, with an infinite number of zeros, it is different from 0. This means that other similar numbers are probably the same, though it does depend on the context. The method involves showing that the two numbers 0.0000000 => 00001 and 0 give completely different output numbers when put into an equation.To show that 0.0000000 => 00001 does not equal 0.Take the equation θ/(sin θ) , where θ is an angle in degrees.For θ = 0.0000000 => 00001, it gives θ/(sin θ) = 180/π = 57.295779513082320876798154814105this is known because a series of increasingly small angles such as 0.0001, 0.0000000001, 0.0000000000000001 etc.give numbers that approach 180/π.But for θ = 0, it gives θ/(sin θ) = 0Therefore 0.0000000 => 00001 does not equal 0.Any thoughts would be appreciated, thanks.

  3. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    Well, that may be so, but this thread is a discussion on the basis that such numbers are worth talking about, so we're assuming they have some meaning before we start. If you say 'there is no such number', then presumably you think this whole thread is pointless.

  4. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    So you have a rule that 'each numerical digit must have it's concrete position'. I suppose you know the positions of all the 9s in 0.99999….. then. But even if you argued that their positions are more concrete than the 1 in the number I used, it's not clear where the rule came from.what I've shown is a series that converges on, or approaches, a number at infinity, and the point is, whatever the existence status of that number at infinity, it isn't zero. And surely whatever its existence status, it's similar to the existence status of the numbers you're talking about.

  5. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    I don't know what you mean by existence, when you say you can prove the existence of your number. But it seems clear enough that if we can talk about numbers with an infinite number of decimal places that all make a difference, then my number and yours are very similar. And my number and yours add up to one, which gives them more common ground.About the position of the 1 in my number, out of all those 9s of yours, there must be one that corresponds to my 1. So whatever problems I have with my number (and God knows it's hard to keep them all in line), you must have the same problems with yours.

  6. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    If you say that one number exists and another doesn't, you need to say what you mean by exists. If you mean exists within mathematics, Gödel showed that mathematics isn't necessarily a self-consistent system, so existing within mathematics isn't necessarily a meaningful concept.If you're not keen on how my number is expressed, perhaps you'd prefer it if I said:an angle θ such that θ/(sin θ) = exactly 180/π. I can prove that this angle is not zero, because θ = 0 gives a different result.

  7. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    Well, it's a matter of taste to some extent. You say you can prove that within a particular artificial system, a number 0.99999999…. exists, but 1 minus that number, or 0.00000….0001 doesn't exist. And yet I've shown that the second number can be expressed as an angle between zero and 90 degrees.This has bearing on the question of whether mathematics is invented or discovered. Are we inventing the rules, or discovering them. When I look at the points above about the digit 1 in my number, I think there's a bit too much inventing going on.

  8. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    See posts above. There's a series of increasingly small angles near zero degrees that approach a number at infinity, but that number is above zero. It's clear that this number gives x/(sin x) = 180/π, because the values approach that number. Whether or not any other values give 180/π makes no difference, but it's interesting to hear it.

  9. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    " 0.999999… exists because every digit in the decimal representation can be specified. If you ask, "what digit is in the 12th place?" Answer: 9. If you ask, "what digit is in the 59th place?" Answer: 9. If you ask, "what digit is in the 623rd place?" Answer: 9. No matter what specific digit you ask about, the answer is always "9". "That's true, and you believe that it's significant.

  10. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    Putting in 0.0001, I get x/(sin x) = 57.295779513111409697664737311509try putting in 0.0000001then 0.00000000000000001.the result will approach 180/[pi], and to me this shows something that is discovered, rather than invented, and has bearing on the similar questions we've been looking at.

  11. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    Sorry, our posts crossed. Yes, I know you think that whether or not a number exists is related to whether or not one can specify the positions of the digits. But the mathematical structure I've shown above hints at a relevant structure that is uncovered, and exists in some way other than just conforming to a made up set of rules.

  12. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    Yes I knew it was 1 radian."This is by definition, not up for debate". This implies that all our definitions are, by definition, correct.What you learned in primary school may or may not be true. But I have said that the context makes a difference sometimes.But the question of comparing a whole number, or a non-negative integer, and another nearby number that approaches it with an infinite series, is not always a clear cut question. And what I've set out has bearing on it, because I've show the two looking different, and looking existent.Don't forget that we learn as we go, the mathematical structures we have are not just a given eternal structure, they were put together bit by bit by finding things, and what we have is, as always, incomplete.

  13. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    Well, there's a symmetry to be pointed out. First, you have 0.9999….. and 1, and these two numbers look the same, or almost the same. People discuss whether they're the same, and whether there's a proof that they are.Then, if you subtract 0.9999….. from 1, you find another pair of numbers – that is, the result of the subtraction, and zero. This pair of numbers can be called 1 – 0.9999…. , and 0.And there's a symmetry between these two pairs of numbers. Each pair may well be in the same relationship, whatever that is. So anything shedding a bit of light on either pair might be relevant. And showing the second pair to be different from each other is relevant.

  14. DMartin
    DMartin says:

    I never said it was a proof, surely even you noticed that. I said it was relevant, and that the context can make a difference. The point that the context makes a difference is borne out by micromass above saying about the context of surreal numbers:"Whether 1=0.9999…  in the surreals depends highly on the definitions for 0.9999… . Some definitions make it equal, others don't."So it's relevant to point out a sequence relating to the second pair of numbers I mentioned, in which there is a distinction between the two of them, because one infinite sequence lands somewhere different from the other.Incidentally, there have been distinctions drawn between different infinities, and it has turned out that they can be compared, and one infinity can turn out to be 'larger' than another. This might intuitively seem impossible, but ways to compare them were found. There is some loose similarity between that and what I've done.

Newer Comments »

Leave a Reply

Want to join the discussion?
Feel free to contribute!

Leave a Reply